David Lewis is well known for his theory of modal realism.

Size: px
Start display at page:

Download "David Lewis is well known for his theory of modal realism."

Transcription

1 Aporia vol. 25 no The Tangled Beard of Modal Realism Kelvin Jensen David Lewis is well known for his theory of modal realism. According to this theory, our world us, the universe we inhabit, and anything that has ever existed therein is just one among many. In fact, modal realism holds that there are countless worlds more or less similar to our own. There is a world, for instance, identical to ours saving one difference: in lieu of wearing a polo shirt today, I wore a button - down shirt. Other worlds are not so similar; one world, for example, consists of planets populated by unicorns. Another is governed by physical laws that permit humans to walk on water. Indeed, for any logically possible state of affairs, there is a world embodying that state of affairs. Since there are infinite possible states of affairs, there are infinite worlds. To be sure, these worlds are spatio - temporally inaccessible and causally isolated from our world, but they exist as fully as our world does. Why would Lewis preach such a bizarre metaphysical doctrine? One sole reason: usefulness (Plurality 3). Lewis believes that his theory resolves important problems in philosophy, specifically in metaphysics, philosophy of language, and philosophy of science. Of particular renown is the solution to a perennial issue in modality, an issue that can be summarized by the following question: what makes modal properties possible? What, for instance, grounds the property I have of possibly wearing a button - down shirt? Modal realism has a ready answer: I possess the property of possibly wearing a button - down shirt because there is a world like ours in every Kelvin Jensen is a senior majoring in philosophy at Brigham Young University. His primary interests include ethics, philosophy of religion, and political philosophy. After graduating next April, Kelvin plans on attending law school. This essay tied for third place in the 2015 David H. Yarn Philosophcal Essay Contest.

2 46 Kelvin Jensen respect except that my counterpart is wearing a button - down shirt. That is, modal properties are grounded in their non - modal realization on Lewisian possible worlds. Whether Lewis s theory can truly explain modal properties and provide the other benefits that Lewis touts has been disputed. However, I shall not argue with Lewis here; for the purposes of this paper, I grant the benefits, all of the benefits, that he ascribes to his theory. I do, however, want to explore an objection that he treats. In his book Counterfactuals, Lewis considers several complaints about modal realism. One qualm relates to Ockham s Razor and can be explained thus: modal realism flies in the face of ontological parsimony, which demands at the very least that one not recklessly postulate the existence of new entities. This prescription is two - pronged: according to quantitative ontological parsimony, one ought not to frivolously postulate additional individual entities; according to qualitative ontological parsimony, one ought not to frivolously postulate additional kinds of entities. Modal realism is thought to run afoul of both senses of parsimony it not only postulates multiple worlds similar to ours, but also postulates multiple worlds different in kind than ours. Inasmuch as ontological parsimony is an important theoretical virtue, modal realism falls short. Lewis s response to this objection is threefold: first, he admits that modal realism disrespects quantitative ontological parsimony but claims that this concession is innocuous (87). Quantitative parsimony is irrelevant to a theory s truth; qualitative parsimony is what matters. Lewis doesn t argue for this position he simply takes it for granted. Second, he insists that modal realism in no way violates qualitative parsimony; after all, possible worlds are not different in kind than the actual world. As Lewis observes, You believe in our actual world already. I ask you to believe in more things of that kind, not in things of some new kind (87). And finally, he presumes that no Ockham s Razor objection can be decisive (87). What he means is that violations of ontological parsimony no matter how flagrant do not, by themselves, warrant rejecting modal realism. I take issue with Lewis s response. Quantitative parsimony is a theoretical virtue, and modal realism does disregard qualitative parsimony. That is, Lewis s theory disrespects both quantitative and qualitative parsimony, both of which are important theoretical considerations. Perhaps a violation of ontological parsimony cannot be decisive, but the violation here is so egregious, even frightful, that we ought to turn our attention to rival theories and remold them to provide the theoretical benefits of modal realism, without the ontological costs. Let s examine the support for my claims. Lewis is not unique in dismissing quantitative parsimony without a hearing. Many philosophers have presumed that quantitative parsimony

3 The Tangled Beard of Modal Realism 47 is simply irrelevant to the truth of a theory. Why is this assumption so prevalent? According to Alan Baker, many reject quantitative parsimony because it doesn t appear to connect to independently recognizable theoretical virtues (248). For instance, qualitative parsimony can be justified by appeals to epistemic conservatism, which holds, at its core, that we ought not to believe in something unless we have good reason to believe in it (248). Syntactical elegance the other strand of Ockham s Razor, a strand which demands simplicity in a theory s basic principles or axioms can be justified on pragmatic grounds. A theory that is syntactically elegant is easier to use or manipulate, and is generally more comprehensible (248). From which theoretical virtue can quantitative parsimony be derived? It can t be derived from epistemic conservatism, for quantitative parsimony doesn t have to do with the postulation of new kinds of entities or mechanisms. Rather, it postulates additional entities of the kinds in which we already believe. Nor does it seem likely that quantitative parsimony can be derived from pragmatic concerns. Thus, inasmuch as quantitative parsimony can t be tied to any obvious theoretical virtue, Lewis is right quantitative parsimony ought to be jettisoned. It may be true that quantitative parsimony isn t justified by appeals to some recognizable theoretical virtue. But I think it can be justified by appeals to the workings of nature. Nature generally uses the simplest means to achieve her ends, and this fact justifies the prescription to keep down the number of individual entities, even if these entities are not different in kind from those in which we believe. If nature uses the simplest means to accomplish her purposes, quantitatively parsimonious theories are more likely to be true ceteris paribus. An example may prove illustrative: in the early twentieth century, physicists observed a puzzling aspect of beta decay, a type of radioactive decay in which an electron is emitted from a nucleus. Upon emission of the electron, the energy of the nucleus decreased by more energy than could be ascribed to the emitted electron. This result bemused scientists, who had anticipated that the diminution of energy in the nucleus would be equivalent to the energy of the emitted electron. Wolfgang Pauli attempted to resolve the discrepancy by conjecturing the existence of a neutrally charged particle a neutrino emitted concomitantly with the electron. This neutrino, Pauli reasoned, would possess an energy mass equal to the difference between the energy loss of the nucleus and the energy of the emitted electron. Pauli s theory was accepted, and the existence of his neutrino was empirically confirmed many years later. Two features of this example stand out: the quantity of neutrinos actually emitted from the atom, and the quantity of neutrinos Pauli postulated. Only one neutrino was emitted from the anomalous atom. Had the atom emitted two neutrinos, each possessing half of the energy of the original,

4 48 Kelvin Jensen nature could have achieved the same results (Nolan 333). Indeed, nature could have achieved the same results with three neutrinos, each possessing a third of the energy of the original; or four; or four hundred. But nature didn t employ four hundred neutrinos, each with one four - hundredth of the necessary charge; she selected one neutrino. In this instance, at least, nature really did use the simplest means to accomplish her ends. Interestingly, Pauli decided to postulate only one neutrino. He could have postulated two neutrinos, each possessing half of the energy needed to account for the discrepancy. This postulation would have yielded the same explanatory power as his first theory (Nolan 333). Or he could have postulated three neutrinos, each possessing a third of the energy needed; or four; or four hundred. Yet Pauli proposed just one neutrino. Pauli was apparently guided by considerations of quantitative parsimony, and even if he wasn t, adherence to quantitative parsimony would have encouraged him to postulate merely one neutrino had he considered the postulation of additional neutrinos. Therefore, it appears that a commitment to quantitative parsimony helps us to select theories more likely to reflect the workings of nature. At this juncture I anticipate two objections: first, although quantitative parsimony got it right in this scenario, it may not always pick out the correct theory. There may be some instances in which nature doesn t use the simplest means to achieve her ends. Moreover, even if there are no such instances, it s not clear that nature will always continue to employ the simplest means. This is a fair objection, and I fear that my response may be somewhat weak. I m not sure that the workings of nature vindicate the utility of quantitative parsimony in every instance, and I certainly don t know whether nature will continue to use the simplest instruments to achieve her ends. However, it does seem true that nature usually employs the simplest means. And the story of Pauli s neutrino is not unique: choosing the lowest quantity possible of individual entities, ceteris paribus, has helped scientists other than Pauli arrive at the truth (Nolan 342). If we are realists about scientific theories, quantitative parsimony is valuable. Second, although I may have shown that quantitative parsimony is an important principle for scientific theories, I may not have shown that quantitate parsimony is an important principle for philosophical theories. Philosophers may not care very much about proposing theories that map to the world; for instance, moral theories describe how the world should be, not how the world is. If quantitative parsimony is valuable because it takes into account the fact that nature generally uses the simplest means, then quantitative parsimony may not be a valuable or even relevant standard for evaluating some philosophical theories.

5 The Tangled Beard of Modal Realism 49 This objection may have merit. The principle of quantitative parsimony may be irrelevant when considering some philosophical theories, but this is not the case when considering theories that seek to inform us about how things are. And modal realism is a theory that purportedly describes how things are; therefore, quantitative parsimony is important to assessments of modal realism. Hence, Lewis is wrong: to concede that modal realism is quantitatively unparsimonious is not innocuous. Rather, the concession indicates a cost of his theory. Let s turn to my second claim, which states that modal realism is qualitatively unparsimonious. As mentioned, Lewis believes that possible worlds are not different in kind than the actual world, so he concludes that modal realism is not qualitatively extravagant. But his premise is patently untrue; many of Lewis s worlds are very different from ours. A plethora of Lewisian worlds are populated by ghosts, witches, unicorns, tooth fairies, talking vacuums, Greek gods and goddesses, and a whole host of creatures whose existence we have rejected. And then there are the worlds themselves. Some of Lewis s worlds have no past or future, others are bereft of regularity, in others there is reverse causation, and in others still there is no causation. Therefore, to believe in modal realism is to believe in copious entities and mechanisms of a very different kind than those in which we now believe. A more glaring violation of qualitative parsimony we would be hard pressed to find. Not so, responds John Divers on Lewis s behalf. In Possible Worlds, Divers admits that belief in modal realism does entail belief in fairy tale - like creatures and obscure mechanisms, but he insists that these things are not of a different kind than the things in our world. For purposes of qualitative parsimony, kind refers to broad ontological categories, like substances or properties (155). And modal realism advocates only two ontological categories: sets and individuals (155). But we already believe in sets and individuals; thus, modal realism doesn t postulate further ontological categories, which signifies that it doesn t posit any new kind of thing. Therefore, concludes Divers, modal realism respects qualitative parsimony. Is Divers response plausible? Not very. First, it s highly unlikely that qualitative parsimony relates merely to Divers broad ontological categories; and second, even if it does, modal realism commits us to the existence of every ontological category, rendering it unparsimonious on Divers own account. Let s consider these assertions. Qualitative parsimony is not treated as if it refers only to Divers general ontological divisions. For example, Cartesian dualism is thought to be less qualitatively parsimonious than material monism, for it posits two substances: mind and body. Mind is thought to be fundamentally different from body, so inasmuch as dualism has no more explanatory

6 50 Kelvin Jensen power than does material monism, dualism is charged with a qualitative parsimony violation, a charge that seems appropriate. But Divers interpretation of qualitative parsimony would not allow this charge. After all, mind is a substance, just as body is. Therefore, dualism does not postulate further ontological categories, according to Divers. Monists go awry in accusing dualism of being qualitatively unparsimonious. But Divers is clearly wrong: monists don t go awry at all in their accusation; qualitative extravagance seems to be a very appropriate criticism of dualism. Indeed, if qualitative parsimony is used only when dealing with theories that postulate what Divers considers to be a further ontological category, it wouldn t be used very much at all. Even if Divers interpretation of qualitative parsimony is correct, Lewis s theory is still qualitatively unparsimonious. For modal realism holds that if it s logically possible for something to exist and this something surely includes ontological categories then it exists. For example, there is nothing logically impossible about the existence of universals, so universals must exist. Indeed, any ontological category whose existence doesn t entail a contradiction is, according to modal realism, an ontological category that exists on some possible world. Therefore, even on Divers interpretation of qualitative parsimony, modal realism is unparsimonious. In fact, it s as unparsimonious as any theory can possibly be. I have shown that quantitative parsimony is an important theoretical consideration, and that modal realism is qualitatively unparsimonious. But Lewis, as mentioned, doesn t believe that ontological parsimony objections are decisive, so perhaps I have spilt much ink for naught. Why would Lewis believe that ontological parsimony violations don t, by themselves, disprove a theory? One might think that an ontological parsimony objection is decisive to a theory only if there exists a rival theory possessing equal explanatory power. If we didn t insert this condition, a parsimony objection could preclude the acceptance of correct theories. For instance, Ancient Greek chemistry is more parsimonious than is modern chemistry Empedocles hypothesizes merely four elements (earth, water, air, and fire), but modern chemists hypothesize 110 elements, as shown in the periodic table. Yet no one would accept Ancient Greek chemistry in lieu of modern chemistry; why? Explanatory power; modern chemistry, although more promiscuous, explains a lot more than does Ancient Greek chemistry. Indeed, due to greater explanatory power, we have committed ourselves to many theories that are less ontologically parsimonious than are their predecessors. What this suggests, then, is that the sword of ontological parsimony can t be wielded unless there are competing theories of equal explanatory capability and of greater parsimony. But we don t have

7 The Tangled Beard of Modal Realism 51 such a condition with respect to modal realism: Lewis s theory explains more than does any other rival theory. Hence, an ontological parsimony objection can t be decisive here. I have a qualm with the foregoing argument: to me, it s not clear that ontological parsimony is decisive only when dealing with theories of equal explanatory power. Our adjudications among rival theories indicate that ontological parsimony can be applied to a theory even when its explanatory power is unmatched. Consider the debate about string theory, for example. String theory is an attempt to unify quantum physics with Newtonian physics, which together can explain the motion of any particle. While Newtonian mechanics can explain the motion of macroscopic particles, quantum mechanics is able to account for the motion of microscopic particles. Why do we desire a single, unified theory? Simply put, the axioms of Newtonian and quantum physics contradict each other. So we seek a new theory, one with a consistent axiom system and the explanatory power of both Newtonian and quantum mechanics. Several such theories have been proposed, and we group these all under the category of string theory. Some scientists don t think that any version of string theory resolves the contradictions in Newtonian and quantum mechanics, but some do. But of those who do, few are eager advocates of string theory. What holds them back? Some are held by back by concerns about ontological parsimony (Grandy). The least ontologically promiscuous versions of string theory postulate the existence of seven dimensions; the most promiscuous, twenty six, and existence of twenty six or even seven dimensions is thought to constitute significant ontological baggage. String theory has no peer in terms of explanatory power, but we are hesitant to support such a profligate theory. In other words, we act like ontological parsimony can be decisive, even for a theory that explains more than do its rivals. Thus, if scientific methodology can be used as a guide, we are warranted, on grounds of parsimony, in rejecting a theory of superior explanatory power. In what circumstances is an ontological parsimony objection decisive? Inasmuch as string theory produces discomfort, it does so for two reasons: first, the entities that string theory requires us to believe in are very different from those in which we currently believe; and second, there seems to be a dearth of good reasons to believe them. The first reason strikes me as obvious: we naturally resist a theory which challenges our basic beliefs or assumptions about the world. The second requires some explanation. String theorists don t postulate seven or twenty six dimensions because they actually have any evidence to support the existence of so many dimensions; rather, they postulate a plethora of dimensions because it makes the math of their theory work (Kuhlmann sec. 3). But

8 52 Kelvin Jensen this seems to offend epistemic conservatism, which states that we ought not to believe in something without possessing good reasons. Believing in an entity solely because it provides theoretical benefits does not constitute a very good reason. What all this suggests, then, is that an ontological parsimony objection can be decisive against a theory if the theory possesses a profligate ontology and little evidence to warrant the ontology. I think that modal realism meets these criteria: the ontology is profligate, and the only reason Lewis adduces to believe in possibilia is because they are serviceable (Plurality 3). Thus, it seems that the ontological parsimony objection waged against modal realism is decisive. Where would the rejection of modal realism leave us? It depends. If we think that the benefits of modal realism are must - haves, then we ought to consider rival modal theories (like Plantinga s or Rosen s) and attempt to remold them to provide the benefits that Lewis s does. Indeed, with the plausibility of modal realism shaved off by the blade of Ockham s Razor, this appears to be the only viable option.

9 Works Cited Baker, Alan. Quantitative Parsimony and Explanatory Power. The British Journal for the Philosophy of Science 54.2 (2003): Divers, John. Possible Worlds. New York: Routledge, Grandy, David. Personal Interview. 22 Jan Kuhlmann, Meinard. Quantum Field Theory. The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy. Ed. Edward N. Zalta, Spring Lewis, David. Counterfactuals. Cambridge: Harvard UP, On the Plurality of Worlds. New York: Blackwell Publishing, Nolan, Daniel. Quantitative Parsimony. The British Journal for the Philosophy of Science 48.3 (1997):

10

Truth At a World for Modal Propositions

Truth At a World for Modal Propositions Truth At a World for Modal Propositions 1 Introduction Existentialism is a thesis that concerns the ontological status of individual essences and singular propositions. Let us define an individual essence

More information

Fundamentals of Metaphysics

Fundamentals of Metaphysics Fundamentals of Metaphysics Objective and Subjective One important component of the Common Western Metaphysic is the thesis that there is such a thing as objective truth. each of our beliefs and assertions

More information

Each copy of any part of a JSTOR transmission must contain the same copyright notice that appears on the screen or printed page of such transmission.

Each copy of any part of a JSTOR transmission must contain the same copyright notice that appears on the screen or printed page of such transmission. The Physical World Author(s): Barry Stroud Source: Proceedings of the Aristotelian Society, New Series, Vol. 87 (1986-1987), pp. 263-277 Published by: Blackwell Publishing on behalf of The Aristotelian

More information

Possibility and Necessity

Possibility and Necessity Possibility and Necessity 1. Modality: Modality is the study of possibility and necessity. These concepts are intuitive enough. Possibility: Some things could have been different. For instance, I could

More information

I. Scientific Realism: Introduction

I. Scientific Realism: Introduction I. Scientific Realism: Introduction 1. Two kinds of realism a) Theory realism: scientific theories provide (or aim to provide) true descriptions (and explanations). b) Entity realism: entities postulated

More information

How Successful Is Naturalism?

How Successful Is Naturalism? How Successful Is Naturalism? University of Notre Dame T he question raised by this volume is How successful is naturalism? The question presupposes that we already know what naturalism is and what counts

More information

How Do We Know Anything about Mathematics? - A Defence of Platonism

How Do We Know Anything about Mathematics? - A Defence of Platonism How Do We Know Anything about Mathematics? - A Defence of Platonism Majda Trobok University of Rijeka original scientific paper UDK: 141.131 1:51 510.21 ABSTRACT In this paper I will try to say something

More information

Luck, Rationality, and Explanation: A Reply to Elga s Lucky to Be Rational. Joshua Schechter. Brown University

Luck, Rationality, and Explanation: A Reply to Elga s Lucky to Be Rational. Joshua Schechter. Brown University Luck, Rationality, and Explanation: A Reply to Elga s Lucky to Be Rational Joshua Schechter Brown University I Introduction What is the epistemic significance of discovering that one of your beliefs depends

More information

Some Good and Some Not so Good Arguments for Necessary Laws. William Russell Payne Ph.D.

Some Good and Some Not so Good Arguments for Necessary Laws. William Russell Payne Ph.D. Some Good and Some Not so Good Arguments for Necessary Laws William Russell Payne Ph.D. The view that properties have their causal powers essentially, which I will here call property essentialism, has

More information

DO WE NEED A THEORY OF METAPHYSICAL COMPOSITION?

DO WE NEED A THEORY OF METAPHYSICAL COMPOSITION? 1 DO WE NEED A THEORY OF METAPHYSICAL COMPOSITION? ROBERT C. OSBORNE DRAFT (02/27/13) PLEASE DO NOT CITE WITHOUT PERMISSION I. Introduction Much of the recent work in contemporary metaphysics has been

More information

Modal Realism, Counterpart Theory, and Unactualized Possibilities

Modal Realism, Counterpart Theory, and Unactualized Possibilities This is the author version of the following article: Baltimore, Joseph A. (2014). Modal Realism, Counterpart Theory, and Unactualized Possibilities. Metaphysica, 15 (1), 209 217. The final publication

More information

Berkeley, Three dialogues between Hylas and Philonous focus on p. 86 (chapter 9) to the end (p. 93).

Berkeley, Three dialogues between Hylas and Philonous focus on p. 86 (chapter 9) to the end (p. 93). TOPIC: Lecture 7.2 Berkeley Lecture Berkeley will discuss why we only have access to our sense-data, rather than the real world. He will then explain why we can trust our senses. He gives an argument for

More information

Branching versus Divergent Possible Worlds

Branching versus Divergent Possible Worlds KRITERION Nr. 19 (2005), pp. 12-20 Branching versus Divergent Possible Worlds Jiří Beňovský University of Fribourg, Switzerland Abstract David Lewis modal counterpart theory falls prey to the famous Saul

More information

Realism and the success of science argument. Leplin:

Realism and the success of science argument. Leplin: Realism and the success of science argument Leplin: 1) Realism is the default position. 2) The arguments for anti-realism are indecisive. In particular, antirealism offers no serious rival to realism in

More information

How Not to Defend Metaphysical Realism (Southwestern Philosophical Review, Vol , 19-27)

How Not to Defend Metaphysical Realism (Southwestern Philosophical Review, Vol , 19-27) How Not to Defend Metaphysical Realism (Southwestern Philosophical Review, Vol 3 1986, 19-27) John Collier Department of Philosophy Rice University November 21, 1986 Putnam's writings on realism(1) have

More information

Has Nagel uncovered a form of idealism?

Has Nagel uncovered a form of idealism? Has Nagel uncovered a form of idealism? Author: Terence Rajivan Edward, University of Manchester. Abstract. In the sixth chapter of The View from Nowhere, Thomas Nagel attempts to identify a form of idealism.

More information

In his book Ethics: Inventing Right and Wrong, J. L. Mackie agues against

In his book Ethics: Inventing Right and Wrong, J. L. Mackie agues against Aporia vol. 16 no. 1 2006 How Queer? RUSSELL FARR In his book Ethics: Inventing Right and Wrong, J. L. Mackie agues against the existence of objective moral values. He does so in two sections, the first

More information

Class 33 - November 13 Philosophy Friday #6: Quine and Ontological Commitment Fisher 59-69; Quine, On What There Is

Class 33 - November 13 Philosophy Friday #6: Quine and Ontological Commitment Fisher 59-69; Quine, On What There Is Philosophy 240: Symbolic Logic Fall 2009 Mondays, Wednesdays, Fridays: 9am - 9:50am Hamilton College Russell Marcus rmarcus1@hamilton.edu I. The riddle of non-being Two basic philosophical questions are:

More information

Van Fraassen: Arguments Concerning Scientific Realism

Van Fraassen: Arguments Concerning Scientific Realism Aaron Leung Philosophy 290-5 Week 11 Handout Van Fraassen: Arguments Concerning Scientific Realism 1. Scientific Realism and Constructive Empiricism What is scientific realism? According to van Fraassen,

More information

Why I Am Not a Property Dualist By John R. Searle

Why I Am Not a Property Dualist By John R. Searle 1 Why I Am Not a Property Dualist By John R. Searle I have argued in a number of writings 1 that the philosophical part (though not the neurobiological part) of the traditional mind-body problem has a

More information

Right-Making, Reference, and Reduction

Right-Making, Reference, and Reduction Right-Making, Reference, and Reduction Kent State University BIBLID [0873-626X (2014) 39; pp. 139-145] Abstract The causal theory of reference (CTR) provides a well-articulated and widely-accepted account

More information

Is the Existence of the Best Possible World Logically Impossible?

Is the Existence of the Best Possible World Logically Impossible? Is the Existence of the Best Possible World Logically Impossible? Anders Kraal ABSTRACT: Since the 1960s an increasing number of philosophers have endorsed the thesis that there can be no such thing as

More information

* Dalhousie Law School, LL.B. anticipated Interpretation and Legal Theory. Andrei Marmor Oxford: Clarendon Press, 1992, 193 pp.

* Dalhousie Law School, LL.B. anticipated Interpretation and Legal Theory. Andrei Marmor Oxford: Clarendon Press, 1992, 193 pp. 330 Interpretation and Legal Theory Andrei Marmor Oxford: Clarendon Press, 1992, 193 pp. Reviewed by Lawrence E. Thacker* Interpretation may be defined roughly as the process of determining the meaning

More information

Resemblance Nominalism and counterparts

Resemblance Nominalism and counterparts ANAL63-3 4/15/2003 2:40 PM Page 221 Resemblance Nominalism and counterparts Alexander Bird 1. Introduction In his (2002) Gonzalo Rodriguez-Pereyra provides a powerful articulation of the claim that Resemblance

More information

Spinoza and the Axiomatic Method. Ever since Euclid first laid out his geometry in the Elements, his axiomatic approach to

Spinoza and the Axiomatic Method. Ever since Euclid first laid out his geometry in the Elements, his axiomatic approach to Haruyama 1 Justin Haruyama Bryan Smith HON 213 17 April 2008 Spinoza and the Axiomatic Method Ever since Euclid first laid out his geometry in the Elements, his axiomatic approach to geometry has been

More information

Fundamental Things: Theory and Applications of Grounding

Fundamental Things: Theory and Applications of Grounding : Theory and Applications of Grounding Louis May 27, 2016 1 Description Much of philosophy consists of proposing and evaluating explanations of a certain sort. We want to know, for instance, what made

More information

In Epistemic Relativism, Mark Kalderon defends a view that has become

In Epistemic Relativism, Mark Kalderon defends a view that has become Aporia vol. 24 no. 1 2014 Incoherence in Epistemic Relativism I. Introduction In Epistemic Relativism, Mark Kalderon defends a view that has become increasingly popular across various academic disciplines.

More information

Rejoinder to Zimmerman. Dean Zimmerman defends a version of Substance Dualism Emergent Dualism

Rejoinder to Zimmerman. Dean Zimmerman defends a version of Substance Dualism Emergent Dualism --from Contemporary Debates in Philosophy of Religion, Michael Peterson, ed. (Oxford: Blackwell Publishers, 2004): 341-343. Rejoinder to Zimmerman Dean Zimmerman defends a version of Substance Dualism

More information

Introduction. I. Proof of the Minor Premise ( All reality is completely intelligible )

Introduction. I. Proof of the Minor Premise ( All reality is completely intelligible ) Philosophical Proof of God: Derived from Principles in Bernard Lonergan s Insight May 2014 Robert J. Spitzer, S.J., Ph.D. Magis Center of Reason and Faith Lonergan s proof may be stated as follows: Introduction

More information

Utilitarianism: For and Against (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1973), pp Reprinted in Moral Luck (CUP, 1981).

Utilitarianism: For and Against (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1973), pp Reprinted in Moral Luck (CUP, 1981). Draft of 3-21- 13 PHIL 202: Core Ethics; Winter 2013 Core Sequence in the History of Ethics, 2011-2013 IV: 19 th and 20 th Century Moral Philosophy David O. Brink Handout #14: Williams, Internalism, and

More information

New Aristotelianism, Routledge, 2012), in which he expanded upon

New Aristotelianism, Routledge, 2012), in which he expanded upon Powers, Essentialism and Agency: A Reply to Alexander Bird Ruth Porter Groff, Saint Louis University AUB Conference, April 28-29, 2016 1. Here s the backstory. A couple of years ago my friend Alexander

More information

Class #14: October 13 Gödel s Platonism

Class #14: October 13 Gödel s Platonism Philosophy 405: Knowledge, Truth and Mathematics Fall 2010 Hamilton College Russell Marcus Class #14: October 13 Gödel s Platonism I. The Continuum Hypothesis and Its Independence The continuum problem

More information

Philip D. Miller Denison University I

Philip D. Miller Denison University I Against the Necessity of Identity Statements Philip D. Miller Denison University I n Naming and Necessity, Saul Kripke argues that names are rigid designators. For Kripke, a term "rigidly designates" an

More information

Can Rationality Be Naturalistically Explained? Jeffrey Dunn. Abstract: Dan Chiappe and John Vervaeke (1997) conclude their article, Fodor,

Can Rationality Be Naturalistically Explained? Jeffrey Dunn. Abstract: Dan Chiappe and John Vervaeke (1997) conclude their article, Fodor, Can Rationality Be Naturalistically Explained? Jeffrey Dunn Abstract: Dan Chiappe and John Vervaeke (1997) conclude their article, Fodor, Cherniak and the Naturalization of Rationality, with an argument

More information

In Part I of the ETHICS, Spinoza presents his central

In Part I of the ETHICS, Spinoza presents his central TWO PROBLEMS WITH SPINOZA S ARGUMENT FOR SUBSTANCE MONISM LAURA ANGELINA DELGADO * In Part I of the ETHICS, Spinoza presents his central metaphysical thesis that there is only one substance in the universe.

More information

Phil 1103 Review. Also: Scientific realism vs. anti-realism Can philosophers criticise science?

Phil 1103 Review. Also: Scientific realism vs. anti-realism Can philosophers criticise science? Phil 1103 Review Also: Scientific realism vs. anti-realism Can philosophers criticise science? 1. Copernican Revolution Students should be familiar with the basic historical facts of the Copernican revolution.

More information

Is there a good epistemological argument against platonism? DAVID LIGGINS

Is there a good epistemological argument against platonism? DAVID LIGGINS [This is the penultimate draft of an article that appeared in Analysis 66.2 (April 2006), 135-41, available here by permission of Analysis, the Analysis Trust, and Blackwell Publishing. The definitive

More information

A Scientific Realism-Based Probabilistic Approach to Popper's Problem of Confirmation

A Scientific Realism-Based Probabilistic Approach to Popper's Problem of Confirmation A Scientific Realism-Based Probabilistic Approach to Popper's Problem of Confirmation Akinobu Harada ABSTRACT From the start of Popper s presentation of the problem about the way for confirmation of a

More information

World without Design: The Ontological Consequences of Natural- ism , by Michael C. Rea.

World without Design: The Ontological Consequences of Natural- ism , by Michael C. Rea. Book reviews World without Design: The Ontological Consequences of Naturalism, by Michael C. Rea. Oxford: Clarendon Press, 2004, viii + 245 pp., $24.95. This is a splendid book. Its ideas are bold and

More information

The Positive Argument for Constructive Empiricism and Inference to the Best

The Positive Argument for Constructive Empiricism and Inference to the Best The Positive Argument for Constructive Empiricism and Inference to the Best Explanation Moti Mizrahi Florida Institute of Technology motimizra@gmail.com Abstract: In this paper, I argue that the positive

More information

Reply to Kit Fine. Theodore Sider July 19, 2013

Reply to Kit Fine. Theodore Sider July 19, 2013 Reply to Kit Fine Theodore Sider July 19, 2013 Kit Fine s paper raises important and difficult issues about my approach to the metaphysics of fundamentality. In chapters 7 and 8 I examined certain subtle

More information

Dualism: What s at stake?

Dualism: What s at stake? Dualism: What s at stake? Dualists posit that reality is comprised of two fundamental, irreducible types of stuff : Material and non-material Material Stuff: Includes all the familiar elements of the physical

More information

Time travel and the open future

Time travel and the open future Time travel and the open future University of Queensland Abstract I argue that the thesis that time travel is logically possible, is inconsistent with the necessary truth of any of the usual open future-objective

More information

Class 6 - Scientific Method

Class 6 - Scientific Method 2 3 Philosophy 2 3 : Intuitions and Philosophy Fall 2011 Hamilton College Russell Marcus I. Holism, Reflective Equilibrium, and Science Class 6 - Scientific Method Our course is centrally concerned with

More information

The Illusion of Scientific Realism: An Argument for Scientific Soft Antirealism

The Illusion of Scientific Realism: An Argument for Scientific Soft Antirealism The Illusion of Scientific Realism: An Argument for Scientific Soft Antirealism Peter Carmack Introduction Throughout the history of science, arguments have emerged about science s ability or non-ability

More information

3. Campos de conocimiento en los que podría ser anunciado (máximo dos):

3. Campos de conocimiento en los que podría ser anunciado (máximo dos): Propuesta de curso o seminario 1. Nombre del profesor: Martin Glazier 2. Nombre del curso o seminario: Explanation and ground 3. Campos de conocimiento en los que podría ser anunciado (máximo dos): Metafísica

More information

Psillos s Defense of Scientific Realism

Psillos s Defense of Scientific Realism Luke Rinne 4/27/04 Psillos and Laudan Psillos s Defense of Scientific Realism In this paper, Psillos defends the IBE based no miracle argument (NMA) for scientific realism against two main objections,

More information

Ultimate Naturalistic Causal Explanations

Ultimate Naturalistic Causal Explanations Ultimate Naturalistic Causal Explanations There are various kinds of questions that might be asked by those in search of ultimate explanations. Why is there anything at all? Why is there something rather

More information

Kantian Humility and Ontological Categories Sam Cowling University of Massachusetts, Amherst

Kantian Humility and Ontological Categories Sam Cowling University of Massachusetts, Amherst Kantian Humility and Ontological Categories Sam Cowling University of Massachusetts, Amherst [Forthcoming in Analysis. Penultimate Draft. Cite published version.] Kantian Humility holds that agents like

More information

The Rightness Error: An Evaluation of Normative Ethics in the Absence of Moral Realism

The Rightness Error: An Evaluation of Normative Ethics in the Absence of Moral Realism An Evaluation of Normative Ethics in the Absence of Moral Realism Mathais Sarrazin J.L. Mackie s Error Theory postulates that all normative claims are false. It does this based upon his denial of moral

More information

Vol. II, No. 5, Reason, Truth and History, 127. LARS BERGSTRÖM

Vol. II, No. 5, Reason, Truth and History, 127. LARS BERGSTRÖM Croatian Journal of Philosophy Vol. II, No. 5, 2002 L. Bergström, Putnam on the Fact-Value Dichotomy 1 Putnam on the Fact-Value Dichotomy LARS BERGSTRÖM Stockholm University In Reason, Truth and History

More information

Huemer s Clarkeanism

Huemer s Clarkeanism Philosophy and Phenomenological Research Philosophy and Phenomenological Research Vol. LXXVIII No. 1, January 2009 Ó 2009 International Phenomenological Society Huemer s Clarkeanism mark schroeder University

More information

The Problem of Identity and Mereological Nihilism. the removal of an assumption of unrestricted mereological composition, and from there a

The Problem of Identity and Mereological Nihilism. the removal of an assumption of unrestricted mereological composition, and from there a 1 Bradley Mattix 24.221 5/13/15 The Problem of Identity and Mereological Nihilism Peter Unger s problem of the many discussed in The Problem of the Many and Derek Parfit s fission puzzle put forth in Reasons

More information

Lecture 9. A summary of scientific methods Realism and Anti-realism

Lecture 9. A summary of scientific methods Realism and Anti-realism Lecture 9 A summary of scientific methods Realism and Anti-realism A summary of scientific methods and attitudes What is a scientific approach? This question can be answered in a lot of different ways.

More information

someone who was willing to question even what seemed to be the most basic ideas in a

someone who was willing to question even what seemed to be the most basic ideas in a A skeptic is one who is willing to question any knowledge claim, asking for clarity in definition, consistency in logic and adequacy of evidence (adopted from Paul Kurtz, 1994). Evaluate this approach

More information

Philosophy 125 Day 21: Overview

Philosophy 125 Day 21: Overview Branden Fitelson Philosophy 125 Lecture 1 Philosophy 125 Day 21: Overview 1st Papers/SQ s to be returned this week (stay tuned... ) Vanessa s handout on Realism about propositions to be posted Second papers/s.q.

More information

The Cosmological Argument, Sufficient Reason, and Why-Questions

The Cosmological Argument, Sufficient Reason, and Why-Questions University of Nebraska - Lincoln DigitalCommons@University of Nebraska - Lincoln Faculty Publications - Department of Philosophy Philosophy, Department of 1980 The Cosmological Argument, Sufficient Reason,

More information

Lecture 7.1 Berkeley I

Lecture 7.1 Berkeley I TOPIC: Lecture 7.1 Berkeley I Introduction to the Representational view of the mind. Berkeley s Argument from Illusion. KEY TERMS/ GOALS: Idealism. Naive realism. Representations. Berkeley s Argument from

More information

Postmodal Metaphysics

Postmodal Metaphysics Postmodal Metaphysics Ted Sider Structuralism seminar 1. Conceptual tools in metaphysics Tools of metaphysics : concepts for framing metaphysical issues. They structure metaphysical discourse. Problem

More information

Postscript to Plenitude of Possible Structures (2016)

Postscript to Plenitude of Possible Structures (2016) Postscript to Plenitude of Possible Structures (2016) The principle of plenitude for possible structures (PPS) that I endorsed tells us what structures are instantiated at possible worlds, but not what

More information

The Question of Metaphysics

The Question of Metaphysics The Question of Metaphysics metaphysics seriously. Second, I want to argue that the currently popular hands-off conception of metaphysical theorising is unable to provide a satisfactory answer to the question

More information

On the Prospects of Confined and Catholic Physicalism. Andreas Hüttemann

On the Prospects of Confined and Catholic Physicalism. Andreas Hüttemann Philosophy Science Scientific Philosophy Proceedings of GAP.5, Bielefeld 22. 26.09.2003 1. Introduction On the Prospects of Confined and Catholic Physicalism Andreas Hüttemann In this paper I want to distinguish

More information

Argumentation Module: Philosophy Lesson 7 What do we mean by argument? (Two meanings for the word.) A quarrel or a dispute, expressing a difference

Argumentation Module: Philosophy Lesson 7 What do we mean by argument? (Two meanings for the word.) A quarrel or a dispute, expressing a difference 1 2 3 4 5 6 Argumentation Module: Philosophy Lesson 7 What do we mean by argument? (Two meanings for the word.) A quarrel or a dispute, expressing a difference of opinion. Often heated. A statement of

More information

Nagel, Naturalism and Theism. Todd Moody. (Saint Joseph s University, Philadelphia)

Nagel, Naturalism and Theism. Todd Moody. (Saint Joseph s University, Philadelphia) Nagel, Naturalism and Theism Todd Moody (Saint Joseph s University, Philadelphia) In his recent controversial book, Mind and Cosmos, Thomas Nagel writes: Many materialist naturalists would not describe

More information

Saving the Substratum: Interpreting Kant s First Analogy

Saving the Substratum: Interpreting Kant s First Analogy Res Cogitans Volume 5 Issue 1 Article 20 6-4-2014 Saving the Substratum: Interpreting Kant s First Analogy Kevin Harriman Lewis & Clark College Follow this and additional works at: http://commons.pacificu.edu/rescogitans

More information

Tuukka Kaidesoja Précis of Naturalizing Critical Realist Social Ontology

Tuukka Kaidesoja Précis of Naturalizing Critical Realist Social Ontology Journal of Social Ontology 2015; 1(2): 321 326 Book Symposium Open Access Tuukka Kaidesoja Précis of Naturalizing Critical Realist Social Ontology DOI 10.1515/jso-2015-0016 Abstract: This paper introduces

More information

K.V. LAURIKAINEN EXTENDING THE LIMITS OF SCIENCE

K.V. LAURIKAINEN EXTENDING THE LIMITS OF SCIENCE K.V. LAURIKAINEN EXTENDING THE LIMITS OF SCIENCE Tarja Kallio-Tamminen Contents Abstract My acquintance with K.V. Laurikainen Various flavours of Copenhagen What proved to be wrong Revelations of quantum

More information

One of the central concerns in metaphysics is the nature of objects which

One of the central concerns in metaphysics is the nature of objects which Of Baseballs and Epiphenomenalism: A Critique of Merricks Eliminativism CONNOR MCNULTY University of Illinois One of the central concerns in metaphysics is the nature of objects which populate the universe.

More information

SIMON BOSTOCK Internal Properties and Property Realism

SIMON BOSTOCK Internal Properties and Property Realism SIMON BOSTOCK Internal Properties and Property Realism R ealism about properties, standardly, is contrasted with nominalism. According to nominalism, only particulars exist. According to realism, both

More information

It turns out that there is an important class of sentences that we have so far pretty much avoided mentioning: modal sentences.

It turns out that there is an important class of sentences that we have so far pretty much avoided mentioning: modal sentences. 1. Introduction 2. Suspicions Regarding Modal Claims 3. Lewisian Realism 3.1. Overview and Motivations 3.2. Problems Metaphysics I: The Nature of Being 0 1. Introduction So far we have focused on the ontological

More information

[3.] Bertrand Russell. 1

[3.] Bertrand Russell. 1 [3.] Bertrand Russell. 1 [3.1.] Biographical Background. 1872: born in the city of Trellech, in the county of Monmouthshire, now part of Wales 2 One of his grandfathers was Lord John Russell, who twice

More information

PHILOSOPHY 4360/5360 METAPHYSICS. Methods that Metaphysicians Use

PHILOSOPHY 4360/5360 METAPHYSICS. Methods that Metaphysicians Use PHILOSOPHY 4360/5360 METAPHYSICS Methods that Metaphysicians Use Method 1: The appeal to what one can imagine where imagining some state of affairs involves forming a vivid image of that state of affairs.

More information

5 A Modal Version of the

5 A Modal Version of the 5 A Modal Version of the Ontological Argument E. J. L O W E Moreland, J. P.; Sweis, Khaldoun A.; Meister, Chad V., Jul 01, 2013, Debating Christian Theism The original version of the ontological argument

More information

Copan, P. and P. Moser, eds., The Rationality of Theism, London: Routledge, 2003, pp.xi+292

Copan, P. and P. Moser, eds., The Rationality of Theism, London: Routledge, 2003, pp.xi+292 Copan, P. and P. Moser, eds., The Rationality of Theism, London: Routledge, 2003, pp.xi+292 The essays in this book are organised into three groups: Part I: Foundational Considerations Part II: Arguments

More information

What Matters in (Naturalized) Metaphysics?

What Matters in (Naturalized) Metaphysics? Essays in Philosophy Volume 13 Issue 1 Philosophical Methodology Article 13 January 2012 What Matters in (Naturalized) Metaphysics? Sophie R. Allen University of Oxford, UK Follow this and additional works

More information

THE MORAL ARGUMENT. Peter van Inwagen. Introduction, James Petrik

THE MORAL ARGUMENT. Peter van Inwagen. Introduction, James Petrik THE MORAL ARGUMENT Peter van Inwagen Introduction, James Petrik THE HISTORY OF PHILOSOPHICAL DISCUSSIONS of human freedom is closely intertwined with the history of philosophical discussions of moral responsibility.

More information

BOOK REVIEWS. Duke University. The Philosophical Review, Vol. XCVII, No. 1 (January 1988)

BOOK REVIEWS. Duke University. The Philosophical Review, Vol. XCVII, No. 1 (January 1988) manner that provokes the student into careful and critical thought on these issues, then this book certainly gets that job done. On the other hand, one likes to think (imagine or hope) that the very best

More information

Chapter Six. Putnam's Anti-Realism

Chapter Six. Putnam's Anti-Realism 119 Chapter Six Putnam's Anti-Realism So far, our discussion has been guided by the assumption that there is a world and that sentences are true or false by virtue of the way it is. But this assumption

More information

DEFEASIBLE A PRIORI JUSTIFICATION: A REPLY TO THUROW

DEFEASIBLE A PRIORI JUSTIFICATION: A REPLY TO THUROW The Philosophical Quarterly Vol. 58, No. 231 April 2008 ISSN 0031 8094 doi: 10.1111/j.1467-9213.2007.512.x DEFEASIBLE A PRIORI JUSTIFICATION: A REPLY TO THUROW BY ALBERT CASULLO Joshua Thurow offers a

More information

CHRISTIANITY AND THE NATURE OF SCIENCE J.P. MORELAND

CHRISTIANITY AND THE NATURE OF SCIENCE J.P. MORELAND CHRISTIANITY AND THE NATURE OF SCIENCE J.P. MORELAND I. Five Alleged Problems with Theology and Science A. Allegedly, science shows there is no need to postulate a god. 1. Ancients used to think that you

More information

Session One: Identity Theory And Why It Won t Work Marianne Talbot University of Oxford 26/27th November 2011

Session One: Identity Theory And Why It Won t Work Marianne Talbot University of Oxford 26/27th November 2011 A Romp Through the Philosophy of Mind Session One: Identity Theory And Why It Won t Work Marianne Talbot University of Oxford 26/27th November 2011 1 Session One: Identity Theory And Why It Won t Work

More information

Perception and Mind-Dependence: Lecture 2

Perception and Mind-Dependence: Lecture 2 1 Recap Perception and Mind-Dependence: Lecture 2 (Alex Moran, apm60@ cam.ac.uk) According to naïve realism: (1) the objects of perception are ordinary, mindindependent things, and (2) perceptual experience

More information

Van Inwagen's modal argument for incompatibilism

Van Inwagen's modal argument for incompatibilism University of Windsor Scholarship at UWindsor Critical Reflections Essays of Significance & Critical Reflections 2015 Mar 28th, 2:00 PM - 2:30 PM Van Inwagen's modal argument for incompatibilism Katerina

More information

Comments on Truth at A World for Modal Propositions

Comments on Truth at A World for Modal Propositions Comments on Truth at A World for Modal Propositions Christopher Menzel Texas A&M University March 16, 2008 Since Arthur Prior first made us aware of the issue, a lot of philosophical thought has gone into

More information

The belief in the existence of an omniscient, omnipotent and benevolent God is inconsistent with the existence of human suffering. Discuss.

The belief in the existence of an omniscient, omnipotent and benevolent God is inconsistent with the existence of human suffering. Discuss. The belief in the existence of an omniscient, omnipotent and benevolent God is inconsistent with the existence of human suffering. Discuss. Is he willing to prevent evil, but not able? Then he is not omnipotent.

More information

Problems of Philosophy

Problems of Philosophy Problems of Philosophy Dr Desh Raj Sirswal, Assistant Professor(Philosophy), P.G. Govt. College for Girls, Sector-11, Chandigarh http://drsirswal.webs.com Introduction Instead of being treated as a single,

More information

A note on science and essentialism

A note on science and essentialism A note on science and essentialism BIBLID [0495-4548 (2004) 19: 51; pp. 311-320] ABSTRACT: This paper discusses recent attempts to use essentialist arguments based on the work of Kripke and Putnam to ground

More information

Saul Kripke, Naming and Necessity

Saul Kripke, Naming and Necessity 24.09x Minds and Machines Saul Kripke, Naming and Necessity Excerpt from Saul Kripke, Naming and Necessity (Harvard, 1980). Identity theorists have been concerned with several distinct types of identifications:

More information

Metametaphysics. New Essays on the Foundations of Ontology* Oxford University Press, 2009

Metametaphysics. New Essays on the Foundations of Ontology* Oxford University Press, 2009 Book Review Metametaphysics. New Essays on the Foundations of Ontology* Oxford University Press, 2009 Giulia Felappi giulia.felappi@sns.it Every discipline has its own instruments and studying them is

More information

Stout s teleological theory of action

Stout s teleological theory of action Stout s teleological theory of action Jeff Speaks November 26, 2004 1 The possibility of externalist explanations of action................ 2 1.1 The distinction between externalist and internalist explanations

More information

Generic truth and mixed conjunctions: some alternatives

Generic truth and mixed conjunctions: some alternatives Analysis Advance Access published June 15, 2009 Generic truth and mixed conjunctions: some alternatives AARON J. COTNOIR Christine Tappolet (2000) posed a problem for alethic pluralism: either deny the

More information

Moral Objectivism. RUSSELL CORNETT University of Calgary

Moral Objectivism. RUSSELL CORNETT University of Calgary Moral Objectivism RUSSELL CORNETT University of Calgary The possibility, let alone the actuality, of an objective morality has intrigued philosophers for well over two millennia. Though much discussed,

More information

Copyright 2015 by KAD International All rights reserved. Published in the Ghana

Copyright 2015 by KAD International All rights reserved. Published in the Ghana Copyright 2015 by KAD International All rights reserved. Published in the Ghana http://kadint.net/our-journal.html The Problem of the Truth of the Counterfactual Conditionals in the Context of Modal Realism

More information

The cosmological argument (continued)

The cosmological argument (continued) The cosmological argument (continued) Remember that last time we arrived at the following interpretation of Aquinas second way: Aquinas 2nd way 1. At least one thing has been caused to come into existence.

More information

Searle vs. Chalmers Debate, 8/2005 with Death Monkey (Kevin Dolan)

Searle vs. Chalmers Debate, 8/2005 with Death Monkey (Kevin Dolan) Searle vs. Chalmers Debate, 8/2005 with Death Monkey (Kevin Dolan) : Searle says of Chalmers book, The Conscious Mind, "it is one thing to bite the occasional bullet here and there, but this book consumes

More information

Van Fraassen: Arguments concerning scientific realism

Van Fraassen: Arguments concerning scientific realism Van Fraassen: Arguments concerning scientific realism 1. Scientific realism and constructive empiricism a) Minimal scientific realism 1) The aim of scientific theories is to provide literally true stories

More information

WHY THERE REALLY ARE NO IRREDUCIBLY NORMATIVE PROPERTIES

WHY THERE REALLY ARE NO IRREDUCIBLY NORMATIVE PROPERTIES WHY THERE REALLY ARE NO IRREDUCIBLY NORMATIVE PROPERTIES Bart Streumer b.streumer@rug.nl In David Bakhurst, Brad Hooker and Margaret Little (eds.), Thinking About Reasons: Essays in Honour of Jonathan

More information

The Theory of Reality: A Critical & Philosophical Elaboration

The Theory of Reality: A Critical & Philosophical Elaboration 55 The Theory of Reality: A Critical & Philosophical Elaboration Anup Kumar Department of Philosophy Jagannath University Email: anupkumarjnup@gmail.com Abstract Reality is a concept of things which really

More information

Truth and Modality - can they be reconciled?

Truth and Modality - can they be reconciled? Truth and Modality - can they be reconciled? by Eileen Walker 1) The central question What makes modal statements statements about what might be or what might have been the case true or false? Normally

More information

DESCARTES ONTOLOGICAL PROOF: AN INTERPRETATION AND DEFENSE

DESCARTES ONTOLOGICAL PROOF: AN INTERPRETATION AND DEFENSE DESCARTES ONTOLOGICAL PROOF: AN INTERPRETATION AND DEFENSE STANISŁAW JUDYCKI University of Gdańsk Abstract. It is widely assumed among contemporary philosophers that Descartes version of ontological proof,

More information