BIAS AND REASONING: HAIDT S THEORY OF MORAL JUDGMENT

Size: px
Start display at page:

Download "BIAS AND REASONING: HAIDT S THEORY OF MORAL JUDGMENT"

Transcription

1 BIAS AND REASONING: HAIDT S THEORY OF MORAL JUDGMENT S. MATTHEW LIAO New York University, 285 Mercer Street, Room 1005, New York, NY 10003, USA; e- mail: matthew.liao@nyu.edu; February 10, 2010

2 Bias and Reasoning: Haidt s Theory of Moral Judgment Abstract According to Haidt s Social Intuitionist Model (SIM) of moral judgment, most moral judgments are generated by the intuitive process and the purpose of reasoning is to provide a post hoc and biased basis for justification. The SIM is of great importance for moral philosophers because if the SIM were an accurate description of how we arrive at our moral judgments, the evidential weight of most of our moral judgments may be undercut. In this paper, I question Haidt s claim that reasoning provides a biased basis for justification by challenging his claim that reasoning is biased. After presenting the tendencies that, according to Haidt, make reasoning biased, I draw on the literature on epistemic justification to show that these tendencies are not always biases. If I am right, it is premature to claim that our reasoning is biased, and that the purpose of reasoning is to provide a biased basis for justification. Keywords: moral judgment; moral intuitions; Social Intuitionist Model; Jonathan Haidt; cognitive biases 2

3 Bias and Reasoning: Haidt s Theory of Moral Judgment 1. Haidt s Social Intuitionist Model A topic of significant interest among social psychologists today is the extent to which intuitions, as opposed to reasoning, play a role in determining moral judgments (Haidt, 2001; Greene and Haidt, 2002; Pizarro and Bloom, 2003). Labelling the automatic, effortless, rapid process of intuitions as System 1, and the controlled, effortful, slow process of reasoning as System 2, a dominant perspective in developmental psychology following the works of Piaget and Kohlberg has been that our moral judgments are the products of System 2 (Kohlberg 1969; Piaget 1932). This is the so-called Rationalist Model of moral judgment. Recently, however, some social psychologists have proposed that at least some of our moral judgments are the product of System 1. In fact, some have even argued that moral judgments arise predominantly as a result of the intuitive process, and the purpose of reasoning appears not to generate moral judgments, but to provide a post hoc and biased basis for justification. In particular, in a series of work, Jonathan Haidt and his collaborators have defended the Social Intuitionist Model (SIM) of moral judgment (Haidt, 2001; Haidt 2007; Haidt and Bjorklund 2007a; Haidt and Bjorklund 2007b). According to the SIM, moral judgments are initially the product of nonconscious automatic intuitive processing. Conscious reasoning then takes place and is typically occupied by the task of justifying whatever intuitions that happen to be presented to the consciousness in a biased, non-truth seeking way. To support the SIM, Haidt, among other things, appeals to the phenomenon of moral dumbfounding (Haidt and Hersh, 2001). Moral dumbfounding occurs when 3

4 people have moral convictions that they are incapable of justifying, but which they nevertheless continue to hold. For instance, Haidt presents the following case in a survey: Julie and Mark are brother and sister. They are travelling together in France on summer vacation from college. One night they are staying alone in a cabin near the beach. They decide that it would be interesting and fun if they tried making love. At the very least it would be a new experience for each of them. Julie was already taking birth control pills, but Mark uses a condom too, just to be safe. They both enjoy making love, but they decide not to do it again. They keep that night as a special secret, which makes them feel even closer to each other. What do you think about that? Was it OK for them to make love? (Haidt, 2001, p. 814) Haidt found that most people regarded the action of Julie and Mark as immoral. When asked to justify their judgment, people typically referred to the possibility of inbreeding and the possible psychological harm to the siblings. However, when it was pointed out to them that in this case, it is stipulated that birth control had been used and that there was no psychological harm to the siblings, Haidt found that many would nevertheless continue to insist that the activity of the siblings was morally wrong. Haidt discovered in particular that some people would make up reasons, sometimes bad ones, to justify their condemnation, while others would concede that they cannot provide any further justification for their judgments (Haidt, 2006, p. 64; Haidt, Bjorklund and Murphy, unpublished). According to Haidt, since these individuals were offering bad reasons or 4

5 were not able to provide any further justification in support of their judgments, it does not seem plausible to hold that their judgments were generated by reasoning. Instead, it seems more likely that these individuals were using reasoning to justify their intuitions in a post hoc and biased way (Haidt, 2001, p. 822). Haidt claims that in fact most moral judgments arise in this manner. The SIM does include the possibility of using reasoning to influence our judgments and using private reflection to influence our initial intuitions, which can then directly generate new future judgments and intuitions. However, Haidt argues that in reality these are rare occurrences (2001, p. 815). Instead, according to Haidt, the revision of our moral judgment occurs primarily through social interaction, in which other people s post hoc reasoning evoke new moral intuitions in us. 2. Post Hoc Reasons and Motivated Reasoning To appreciate the novelty and the radicalness of Haidt s theory of moral judgment, it is useful to contrast the SIM with two other models of moral judgment. 1 The first is the 1 On the dual process model of moral judgment, if one were to take into consideration the relative causal contributions of the intuitive and reasoning processes, as well as the goodness/badness of these processes understood in terms of truth-seeking/biases, one can identify twelve different models of moral judgment: S1 B = S2 B S1 G = S2 G S1 G = S2 B S1 B = S2 G S1 B > S2 B S1 G > S2 G S1 G > S2 B S1 B > S2 G S1 B < S2 B S1 G < S2 G S1 G < S2 B S1 B < S2 G Key: S1 = System 1; S2 = System 2; = means roughly equal causal contribution; > means greater causal contribution; < means lesser causal contribution; B = bad, understood in terms of biases; G = good, understood in terms of truth-seeking. The SIM seems to be S1 G > S2 B, though sometimes Haidt could be 5

6 Reflective Equilibrium Model, according to which we use both System 1 and System 2 to develop and form our moral judgments. This model is akin to (if not the same as) the standard philosophical practice of using intuitions to test against theories and using theories to test against intuitions in order to reach some sort of coherence (Rawls, 1971). On the Reflective Equilibrium Model, we often use intuitions to test against reasoning and reasoning to test against intuitions in order to reach some sort of coherent moral judgment. Unlike the SIM, the Reflective Equilibrium Model does not claim that moral judgments arise predominantly as a result of the intuitive process or that the purpose of reasoning is to provide a post hoc and biased basis for justification. Another model that is also different from the SIM is what might be called the Benign Social Intuitionist Model, according to which moral judgments arise predominantly as a result of the intuitive process but reasoning can sometimes help solve problems that the intuitive process cannot solve or help improve our moral judgments by providing further justifications for our initial intuitive judgments. 2 As we shall see, Haidt explicitly rejects the Benign Social Intuitionist Model. Haidt s novel claims are that we use predominantly System 1 to form our moral judgments, and that System 2 is primarily used for providing a post hoc and biased basis for justification. read as holding S1 B > S2 B. The Benign Social Intuitionist Model is S1 G > S2 G, which Haidt rejects. He certainly does not hold S1 B > S2 G. The Reflective Equilibrium Model could be something like S1 G = S2 G. And the Rationalist Model could be S1 G < S2 G or more radically, S1 B < S2 G. 2 One might get the Benign Social Intuitionist Model if one applies Gigerenzer s view on dual processing to moral judgments (Gigerenzer and Todd, 1999). Steve Clarke (2008) s SIM S could support a Benign Social Intuitionist Model, though SIM S is concerned only with the structure of the SIM and not the goodness/badness understood in terms of truth-seeking/biases of the intuitive and the reasoning processes. 6

7 The SIM is of great importance for moral philosophers because if it were an accurate description of how we arrive at our moral judgments, the evidential weight of most of our moral judgments may be undercut. Indeed, as Gibbard (2008, p. 14) observes in his Berkeley Tanner Lectures, if intuitions are the sorts of states that figure in Haidt s picture, [that is, if they are ones that reach moral conclusions all by themselves,] why place any stock in them? Or, Kennett and Fine (2009) argue that the SIM challenges our normative conception of ourselves as agents capable of grasping and responding to reasons, and that there can be no real moral judgments in the absence of a capacity for reflective shaping and endorsement of moral judgments. In the literature critiquing Haidt s work, Fine (2006, p. 95) has helpfully observed that Haidt makes two types of claims regarding our reasoning: the motivated nature of our reasoning ( the reasoning process is more like a lawyer defending a client than a judge or scientist seeking truth (2001, 820); and the post hoc nature of reasons ( the reasoning process readily constructs justifications of intuitive judgments, causing the illusion of objective reasoning (2001, 822)) (my italics). Most of the SIM s critics have focused on the post hoc nature of reasons. For instance, a number of writers have pointed out that intuitive judgments may reflect the automatization of judgments based on prior moral reasoning (Saltzstein and Kasachkoff, 2004), and that moral reasoning can disrupt the automatic process of 7

8 judgment formation described by the SIM, either by a slow, intentional, deliberative and effortful after-the-fact correction, or by an up-front preconscious control (Fine, 2006). In response, Haidt has accepted these possibilities, but he claims that these occurrences are rare (Haidt and Bjorklund, 2007a). However, it might be asked, what evidence does Haidt have that the occurrences of reasoning prior to intuitive judgments are in fact rare? After all, it is not implausible to think that the phenomenon of moral dumbfounding occurs only in a handful of special cases. For example, arguably, Haidt s case of Julie and Mark discussed above is a special case of incest constructed by Haidt. In more mundane cases of incest, the possibility of inbreeding and the possible psychological harm to the sibling would seem to support and justify the judgment that incest is wrong. In discussing how common private reflection takes place, Haidt concedes that there is not at present evidence that would allow an answer to this question (Haidt, 2003). This said, to be fair to Haidt, Haidt s critics also have not shown that the occurrences of reasoning prior to intuitive judgments are not rare. So the debate on this point appears to be at a stand-still at least for now. However, Haidt s claim is not just that reasoning is post-hoc, but that it is also biased. 3 So, even if we cannot yet settle the issue of whether moral judgments arise predominantly as a result of the intuitive process, Haidt could still maintain the other aspect of the SIM, according to which the purpose of reasoning is to provide a biased basis for justification. 3 Some might think that the motivated nature of reasoning is note essential to the SIM. However, in personal communication, Haidt has explicitly said that it is essential to his view that reasoning is biased. Also, recall Fine s point that Haidt makes two types of claims regarding our reasoning: the post-hoc nature of reasons and the motivated nature of reasoning. In addition, Haidt has said that reasoning is biased in numerous places in his writings (see, e.g., Haidt, 2006, Chapter 4). Furthermore, if Haidt did not regard reasoning as being biased, the SIM would not be all that different from, e.g., the Benign Social Intuitionist Model, which Haidt explicitly rejects. 8

9 In response to this point, Fine has argued that we can also be motivated to be truth-seeking (2006, p. 94), and Neil Levy could be read as proposing that the biases Haidt has in mind can be cancelled out as long as reasoning is put in the open and subjected to a community-wide scrutiny led by moral experts (2006). However, to support the idea that reasoning is biased, Haidt has appealed to the vast literature on motivated reasoning and biases. If that literature is to be believed, it is not obvious that biases can be so easily cancelled out, as, e.g., Levy seems to suppose. For example, there are studies that show that people become more biased in groups (Kerr, MacCoun, and Kramer, 1996). Also, there are studies that show that peer review may be subject to the kinds of motivated reasoning that are seen in individuals (Mahoney, 1977). Indeed, some people have also speculated that theoretical physics in the last 20 years has been dominated by advocates of string theories at the expense of other theories (Smolin, 2006). If biases can take place at the community-wide level just as they can at the individual level, community-wide scrutiny may only have limited effects in cancelling out biases. In the following, I shall examine in greater detail the literature on motivated reasoning and biases, which forms the basis for Haidt s claim that reasoning is biased. I begin by presenting the tendencies that, according to Haidt, make reasoning biased. After noting that intuitions are equally vulnerable to these tendencies, and that there might be debiasing strategies that could be employed to counter these tendencies on behalf of reasoning, I then point out that Haidt and others simply assume that these tendencies are biases. Drawing on the literature in epistemology on epistemic justification, I argue that these tendencies are not always biases. If this is correct, it is premature to claim that our 9

10 reasoning is biased, and that the purpose of reasoning is to provide a biased basis for justification. 3. Haidt s Case for the Biased Nature of Reasoning On the Benign Social Intuitionist Model, moral judgments arise predominantly as a result of the intuitive process, but reasoning is the smarter, but cognitively more expensive, process that is employed whenever the intuitive process is unable to solve a problem cheaply. Haidt argues though that empirical evidence does not support this model (2001, p. 820). Referring to the literature on motivated reasoning, Haidt points to two factors that, according to him, make reasoning biased. The first is the relatedness motives (Haidt, 2001, p. 821). According to these motives, we tend to be motivated to agree with our friends, and, as a result, we tend actually to agree with our friends. Haidt cites, for example, studies by Chaiken, Shechter and Chaiken (1996) that found that people who expected to discuss an issue with a partner whose attitudes were known tended to express attitudes that were evaluatively consistent with the partner's opinion. As Chaiken et al. explain, sometimes we are motivated to agree with our friends just because we do not want to come across as being disagreeable. For example, when the views of our friends are unknown, we might employ a moderate opinions minimize disagreement heuristic in order to have a smooth interaction with such a friend (Chen, Shechter, and Chaiken, 1996, p. 263). Or, when the views of our friends are known, we might employ a go along to get along heuristic to serve the same goal (Chen, Shechter, and Chaiken, 1996, p. 263). As Haidt says, the existence of such a motive means that the mere fact that your friend expresses a moral 10

11 judgment against X is often sufficient to cause in you a critical attitude toward X, which, according to Haidt, is a kind of bias (2001, p. 821). The second kind of factor that makes reasoning biased is what Haidt calls the coherence motives (2001, p. 821). According to these motives, we tend to try to keep our attitudes and beliefs congruent with the beliefs and attitudes that are central to our identity, and we tend to dismiss evidence that threatens attitudes and beliefs that are constitutive of our identity. Haidt points, for example, to studies that found that we tend to accept evidence supporting our prior beliefs with less scrutiny and we tend to subject opposing evidence to greater scrutiny. For example, in the classic study by Lord, Ross, and Lepper (1977) in which two groups of people were selected, one strongly in favor of capital punishment and the other strongly opposed to capital punishment, the researchers gave people from both groups some mixed evidence, namely, a piece of new research that suggested that capital punishment was an effective deterrent and a piece of new research that suggested that capital punishment was not an effective deterrent. The researchers found that people tended to regard the research that was consistent with their original views to be better conducted and more convincing than the research that conflicted with their original views. Moreover, the researchers found that people tended to hold on to their initial views even more strongly after having been presented with the mixed evidence. According to Lord, Ross and Lepper, this belief polarization does not seem to be a rational response, because learning about research that conflicted with our views should cause us to have reduced, rather than increased, confidence in our views. Haidt goes on to cite other studies that, according to him, revealed how the relatedness and coherence motives make people act like intuitive lawyers rather than 11

12 intuitive scientists (2001, p. 821). As Haidt explains, he is not trying to demonstrate that people are stupid or irrational (2001, p. 821). Instead, Haidt believes that he is only trying to show that the roots of human intelligence, rationality, and ethical sophistication should not be sought in our ability to search for and evaluate evidence in an open and unbiased way (my italics) (2001, p. 821). 4. Some Initial Defense of Reasoning Haidt is surely correct that reasoning can sometimes be biased. In addition to the possible biasing factors that Haidt had mentioned, we can add to the list the fact that we are not very reliable at detecting correlations; we tend to be overconfident about the power of our reasoning; and so on (Nisbett and Ross, 1980; Trope and Liberman, 1996). Moreover, our cognitive limitations, including limits on our memory and attention, can further contribute to the relative unreliability of our reasoning. However, these concerns should be put in perspective. I shall present four considerations, the last of which I shall discuss in greater detail in the remaining parts of the paper. First, according to those social psychologists whose studies form the basis for Haidt s claim that reasoning is biased, there are three main kinds of motivational underpinnings of information processing (Chaiken, Giner-Sorolla, and Chen, 1996). Haidt has mentioned the relatedness and the coherence motives, but there are also the accuracy motives, which are characterized by a relatively impartial, open-minded treatment of information (Chen, Shechter, Chaiken, 1996, p. 263). While social psychologists believe that we are sometimes or often motivated by the relatedness and the 12

13 coherence motives, they also believe that we are also often motivated by the accuracy motives (Fine, 2006, p. 94). Among other things, these social psychologists have found that even when the relatedness and the coherence motives are activated, the accuracy motives can also remain activated. To give one example, in a study in which the participants are told that introverts are more likely to be successful in order to motivate the participants to rate themselves as being more introverted, it was found that subjects, who were predominantly extraverted to begin with, viewed themselves as less extraverted when they believed introversion to be more desirable, but they still viewed themselves as extraverted (Kunda and Sanitioso, 1989). Pace Haidt, such research suggests that reasoning is receptive to unbiased evidence even when the other motives are activated. Secondly, while our reasoning can be biased, so can our intuitions. As Chaiken et al. (1996, p. 263) have noted, the relatedness and the coherence motives can just as easily influence our intuitions (what they call heuristic processing) as they can our reasoning (what they call systematic processing). If so, even if Haidt were correct that reasoning is biased, intuitions may not fare much better. Note that Haidt may not be too troubled by the idea that our intuitions are also distorted. However, at least in some of his writings, he seems to think that intuitions can be fairly accurate. For example, he says that Rather than following the ancient Greeks in worshiping reason, we should instead look for the roots of human intelligence, rationality, and virtue in what the mind does best: perception, intuition, and other mental operations that are quick, effortless, and generally quite accurate (my italics) (Haidt, 2001, p. 822). Thirdly, psychologists and philosophers have explored the possibility of debiasing strategies for our reasoning (and for our intuitions). For example, Wilson and Brekke 13

14 (1994) offer the following general strategies: First, we must be aware of the biases. Secondly, we must be motivated to correct these biases. Thirdly, even if we were motivated to correct the biases, we must also be aware of the direction and the magnitude of the bias. Finally, we must be aware of whether we have sufficient control over our responses to be able to correct these biases. Or, Bishop and Trout (2005) propose that one should consider explanations for propositions that one does not believe; make statistical judgments in terms of frequencies rather than probabilities; and so on. 4 Levy s idea of distributed cognition may also be considered as a debiasing strategy. These strategies may give us some ideas of the conditions under which we can counter biases. Fourth, Haidt and others simply assume that the relatedness and the coherence motives are biases. But it is worth asking whether they always are, since if they are not, this would undercut Haidt s basis for believing that reasoning is biased. In the remaining part of the paper, I shall examine whether these motives are always biases. To do this, it is important to say more about the concept of bias. 5. Bias and Epistemic Justification According to Wilson and Brekke, who have examined the extensive social psychology literature on bias (or what they call mental contamination ), there have been two general ways of defining bias in this literature (1994, p. 120). According to the first, people who do not use a rule that experts agree is correct are biased (Nisbett and Ross, 1980, p. 13). According to the second, which is Wilson s and Brekke s preferred approach, a judgment, emotion, or behavior is said to be contaminated if it was influenced in an 4 See also (Sinnott-Armstrong, 2006). 14

15 unwanted way (i.e., unwanted by the person whose judgment, emotion, or behavior it is) (1994, p. 120). For our purposes, I believe that we should not use either definition. To see why, consider the first definition. It seems that something can be a bias even if the experts say otherwise (e.g. the alleged bias towards string theory). Or, suppose that being motivated to agree with our friends is a bias. It seems that this would remain a bias even if experts were to say that this is not a bias. The first definition implies though that if experts say that this is not a bias, then it is no longer a bias. Consider the second definition. It seems that something can remain a bias even if it is a wanted influence. For example, suppose again that being motivated to agree with our friends is a bias. However, suppose that I want to be motivated to agree with my friends. Since my judgment is influenced in a wanted way, the second definition implies that I am no longer biased. To be fair, the social psychologists most likely intended for these two definitions to be operational definitions, that is, definitions that can be used in empirical research. Still, neither appears to be adequate as a conceptual definition of bias. So what is an adequate conceptual account of bias? It is beyond the scope of this paper to give a full account of this concept. To offer something that is I think relatively uncontroversial and sufficient for our purpose, I propose that we understand the concept of bias in terms of the vast literature in epistemology on epistemic justification. In particular, if someone, X, is epistemically justified in believing P, then X is not biased about P. And, if X is biased about P, then X is not epistemically justified in believing P. 15

16 On a standard account of epistemic justification, what makes a judgment, P, epistemically justified depends in part on whether one has adequate evidence for P and whether one bases one s judgment that P on that evidence (Alston, 1985). If one has adequate evidence for P and one bases one s judgment for P on that evidence, then one s judgment that P is epistemically justified. If one lacks adequate evidence for P or if one does not base one s judgment that P on some adequate evidence, then one s judgment that P is not epistemically justified. For our purpose, this means that someone who is not biased about P is someone who judges that P with adequate evidence for P and on the basis of that evidence, and someone who is biased about P is someone who judges that P without adequate evidence for P or without basing the judgment that P on some adequate evidence. Here it is worth remembering that epistemic justification does not require true beliefs. That is, one can have epistemically justified false beliefs. This means that two people can be epistemically justified in disagreeing with one another, without being biased, even if one of them is holding a false belief. Let me accept that in some, more general, sense of the term bias, one could be epistemically justified in believing P and still be biased about P. But the kinds of biases at issue here are not these kinds of biases. Consider, for example, why the tendency to be motivated to agree with our friends could be a bias. Arguably, an explanation is that the fact that someone is our friend is typically not the right kind of epistemic evidence that one should be using to base a judgment. If so, there could be a bias in this case precisely because one might not have met the appropriate epistemic standard of justification in basing a judgment on the fact that someone is our friend. Or, consider why the tendency 16

17 to subject one s opponent s views to much greater scrutiny could be a bias. A plausible explanation is that one might be ignoring certain valid evidence against one s own judgment. If so, there could also be a bias in this case precisely because one has not met the appropriate epistemic standard of justification in basing a judgment on selectively chosen evidence. No doubt, more can be said about this matter. But I shall assume that these are the kinds of biases that are at issue here. Note that since the concept of bias in this paper is related to epistemic justification, to vary my choice of words, I shall sometimes refer to someone who is not biased as being epistemically rational and someone who is biased as being epistemically irrational. I shall now consider whether the relatedness and the coherence motives are always biases using this, more adequate, conception of bias. Since the empirical literature on these two motives is vast, I cannot hope to discuss the entire literature here. What I shall aim to do is to offer proof of concept. In particular, I shall consider some of the strongest cases for why these motives appear to be biases and I shall show that even by these lights, these motives are not always biases. 6. Are Relatedness Motives Always Biases? Recall that according to the relatedness motives, we tend to be motivated to agree with our friends, and as a result, we tend actually to agree with our friends. Are these tendencies always biases? Let me mention that I am aware that some of the literature on the relatedness motives suggests that these motives may work for both friends and non-friends alike. However, it seems that if the relatedness motives are pernicious at all, they will be 17

18 particularly pernicious in cases of friends. Moreover, as we have seen, Haidt also focuses on our tendency to agree with our friends. As he says, The existence of motivations to agree with our friends and allies means that we can be directly affected by their judgments (the social persuasion link). The mere fact that your friend expresses a moral judgment against X is often sufficient to cause in you a critical attitude toward X (Haidt, 2001, p. 821). So I shall also focus my discussion on this tendency to agree with our friends. Let us consider first whether the tendency to be motivated to agree with our friends is always a bias. Here is a reason why it is not. A friend is typically someone whose judgments you have reasons to trust in general. That is, you have reasons to trust that when your friend disagrees with you, she will be honest with you, try to familiarize herself with the relevant available evidence that bear on the issue, exercise epistemic virtues such as intelligence and thoughtfulness, and so on. Suppose that you find yourself in a disagreement with your friend about a particular matter. Suppose further that you and she are both fallible and neither has any special epistemic advantage regarding the issue at stake. Can it be epistemically rational for you to reason that because she is your friend and because she disagrees with you, you should suspend your judgment or at least move your judgment towards her judgment? Arguably, it can be epistemically rational to do so. Why? Given that you trust her judgments in general, it can be epistemically rational for you to believe that there is a chance you might be mistaken and that she might be correct on this particular occasion. Given this, it can be epistemically rational for you at least to move your judgment towards her judgment. In other words, it can be epistemically rational for you to be 18

19 motivated to agree with your friend in certain circumstances, because typically a friend is someone whose judgments you trust in general. In contrast, consider someone who is not a friend. Suppose that he is someone whose judgments you neither trust nor distrust in general. Suppose that you find yourself in a disagreement with this person about a particular matter. Suppose further that you and he are both fallible and neither has any special epistemic advantage regarding the issue at stake. Can it be epistemically rational for you to reason that because he is not your friend, you need not suspend your judgment or move your judgment towards his judgment? Again, arguably, it can be epistemically rational to do so. Why? Given that you neither trust nor distrust his judgments in general, it can be epistemically rational for you to believe that there is a chance that he might be mistaken and that you might be correct on this particular occasion. Given this, it can be epistemically rational for you not to suspend your judgment or move your judgment towards his judgment. In other words, it can be epistemically rational for you not to be motivated to agree with someone who is not your friend on certain occasions, because that person might be someone whose judgment you neither trust nor distrust. The general point here is that the relatedness motives merely show that we have a tendency to be motivated to agree with our friends. But one should distinguish between a) our tendency to be motivated to agree with our friends because we want to be harmonious with our friends, and 19

20 b) our tendency to be motivated to agree with our friends because we tend to trust our friends judgments in general. Both a) and b) can explain why we have the tendency to be motivated to agree with our friends. But while a) may be epistemically irrational, b) need not be, since it can be epistemically justified to trust a friend s judgment (e.g. based on how the friend has judged in the past about other matters). Given that a) is Haidt s explanation for why we have the tendency to be motivated to agree with our friends, but b) is a viable possibility and is not epistemically irrational, the fact that we tend to be motivated to agree with our friends need not always be a bias. Note that my claim here is not the strong one that it is never the case that when you are motivated to agree with your friend, you are motivated in this way because you want to agree with her. Instead, my claim is the weaker one that it is not the case that when you are motivated to agree with your friend, you are always motivated in this way because you want to agree with her. Of course, we may also have friends whose judgments in general we do not trust. In those cases, it would certainly be a bias if we were to be motivated to agree with such friends, even when we do not trust their judgments in general. Let us next consider whether the fact that we tend actually to agree with our friends entails that we are biased. Again, it is useful to distinguish two cases. c) We tend to have similar evidence and we tend to treat the evidence in a similar way, because we are friends. 20

21 d) We are friends, because in part we tend to have similar evidence and we tend to treat the evidence in a similar way. c) may indeed involve a bias, but d) need not always involve a bias. The reason is that if our friends happen to have similar evidence as we do and tend to treat them in similar ways as we do, it is not epistemically irrational to have similar judgments as our friends, given that we both possess similar evidence. This is not to say that we cannot and should not disagree with our friends. Nor does it mean that we cannot and should not agree with someone who is not our friend. On a particular occasion, if we have evidence that a friend is wrong, then we are rationally required to disagree with our friend. We would be epistemically irrational on this occasion if we were to suppress the evidence so that we and our friend could agree. Similarly, on a particular occasion, if someone who is not our friend has evidence that we are wrong, then we are rationally required to move towards his judgment. We would be epistemically irrational on this occasion if we were to ignore the evidence just because he is not our friend. However, as long as we are making judgments based on adequate evidence, and as long we and our friends tend to agree because we have similar evidence, our judgments can be epistemically justified even if they tend to be the same. If so, our tendency actually to agree with our friends also need not always be a bias. 7. Are Coherence Motives Always Biases? Recall that the coherence motives are ones according to which we tend to try to keep our attitudes and beliefs congruent with the beliefs and attitudes that are central to our 21

22 identity. As we have seen earlier, a purported strong piece of evidence of this tendency is our tendency to accept evidence supporting our prior beliefs with less scrutiny and to subject opposing evidence to much greater scrutiny. Is this tendency always a bias? Here are a few scenarios in which we might have such a tendency and in which it is not a bias to have such a tendency. Scenario 1: Suppose that you believe P because of E 1, and your opponent believes ~P because of E 2. It may be epistemically rational for you to accept E 1 with less scrutiny, while subjecting E 2 to greater scrutiny, for the following reason. You are already aware of E 1, but you are not aware of E 2. Since epistemic justification requires that you seek the truth about P, you should subject E 2 to greater scrutiny in case E 2 does undermine P. If so, in this scenario, your accepting evidence supporting your prior beliefs with less scrutiny while subjecting opposing evidence to greater scrutiny need not be a bias. Scenario 2: Suppose that you believe P, and your opponent believes ~P. There might be objections to P. However, you are only aware of objections to ~P based on r, s, and t. It may be epistemically rational for you to spend more time thinking about objections to ~P based on r, s, and t rather than objections to P, because you are actually aware of r, s, and t, but you are only aware that there might be objections to P. In other words, it does not seem epistemically irrational for someone to spend more time thinking about objections of which she is aware rather than objections of which she might become aware. 22

23 Of course, suppose that you are only aware that there might be objections to P and that there might be objections to ~P. In such a case, it would seem to be epistemically irrational if you were to spend all your time trying to find objections to ~P and not spend any time trying to find objections to P. Or, suppose that you are aware of objections to P based on x, y, and z, as well as objections to ~P based on r, s, and t. In such a case, it would also seem to be epistemically irrational if you were to spend all your time only thinking about objections to ~P based on r, s, and t, and not objections to P based on x, y, and z. In other words, in cases in which you are symmetrically aware of how much evidence there is against P and against ~P, it would seem to be epistemically irrational to be uneven-handed in your treatment of the evidence. But in cases in which you are asymmetrically aware of how much evidence there is against P and against ~P, it need not be epistemically irrational for you to spend more time thinking about objections of which you are actually aware rather than objections of which you might become aware. If this is right, asymmetric cases would be ones in which your accepting evidence supporting your prior beliefs with less scrutiny, while subjecting opposing evidence to greater scrutiny need not be a bias. Scenario 3: In the belief polarization studies by Lord, Ross and Lepper, two groups with divergent views were presented with mixed evidence, and their views became even more divergent. Can this be epistemically rational? 23

24 To see how it can be, let us begin with a simple case in which two people initially have the same view about a particular matter; they are presented with the same new evidence; and their views diverge rationally. Suppose that A and B both initially believe to the same degree that climate change is a problem. Suppose that A and B then learn that Al Gore has announced in a documentary that climate change is a serious problem. A s and B s views about climate change can rationally diverge in the following way. Suppose that A is a documentary maker. She has previously received memos from credible sources that Al Gore would make a documentary about climate change only if he is certain that there is sufficient evidence that climate change is a serious problem. Upon learning that Al Gore has announced in a documentary that climate change is a serious problem, A may become more certain in an epistemically rational way that climate change really is a serious problem. A s change of view can be epistemically rational because the memos about Al Gore and her knowledge of them are prima facie appropriate epistemic evidence. In contrast, suppose that B is a political historian. Through her independent research, she has found a significant statistical correlation between political candidates who have lost in an election and their trying to reclaim spotlights in the media by making grandiose, but false claims. Upon learning that Al Gore has announced in a documentary that climate change is a serious problem, B may become more skeptical in an epistemically rational manner that climate change is a serious problem. B s change of view can be epistemically rational because her independent research is also prima facie appropriate evidence. 24

25 Here then is a case in which two people with the same initial view about a particular matter can have rationally divergent views about that matter when given the same new evidence. As one can see from the example, this can occur because people can have different, but epistemically rational, background beliefs, which can lead them to hold rationally divergent views when they are presented with the same new evidence. Similar things can be said about the more complex case involving two people with two opposing views, who are presented with mixed evidence and whose views diverge even further as a result. Suppose that A believes that consequentialism is the correct moral theory, and B believes that consequentialism is not the correct morally theory. Suppose that A and B are then presented with some mixed evidence, namely, an argument in favor of consequentialism (F 1 ) and an argument against consequentialism (F 2 ). F 1 : Consequentialism is the correct moral theory because a correct moral theory would say that when we are faced with the decision to kill one to save 100, we should kill the one to save the 100, and consequentialism does say this. F 2 : Consequentialism is not the correct moral theory because a correct moral theory should not be too demanding and consequentialism is too demanding. Here is how A and B can rationally accept evidence that supports their respective views and rationally dismiss the evidence against their respective views, which would result in 25

26 their views diverging even further, without being biased. Suppose that A believes independently of the debate about the correctness of consequentialism and with appropriate epistemic justification that morality should be demanding and that when we are faced with the decision to kill one to save 100, we should kill the one to save the 100. When faced with F 1, A will accept it as confirming his belief that consequentialism is the correct moral theory, since it is consistent with A s independent and epistemically justified belief that when we are faced with the decision to kill one to save 100, we should kill the one to save the 100. When faced with F 2, A will reject it, since it conflicts with A s independent and epistemically justified belief that morality should be demanding. In contrast, suppose that B believes independently of the debate about the correctness of consequentialism and with appropriate epistemic justification that morality should not be demanding and that when we are faced with the decision to kill one to save 100, we should not kill the one to save the 100. When faced with F 1, B will reject it, since it conflicts with B s independent and epistemically justified belief that when we are faced with the decision to kill one to save 100, we should not kill the one to save the 100. When faced with F 2, B will accept it, as it is consistent with B s independent and epistemically justified belief that morality should not be demanding. This case illustrates then that two people with opposing views can, without being biased, rationally accept evidence that supports their respective views and rationally dismiss evidence against their respective views, which can then result in their views diverging even further. Similar to the previous case, this can occur because people can 26

27 have different, but epistemically justified, background beliefs, which can lead them to hold rationally divergent views when they are presented with new but mixed evidence. Note that I am not arguing that two people with opposing views are never biased when they accept evidence that supports their respective views and dismiss evidence against their respective views, which results in their views diverging even further. My limited claim is that finding belief polarization does not mean that the individuals involved are therefore biased. If this is right, our tendency to scrutinize other people s views to a greater degree than our own views and the coherence motives generally need also not always be biases. At this point, Haidt may accept that in theory, the relatedness and the coherence motives are not always biases, but he may say that in practice, these motives always are biases. This is an empirical point. As far as I am aware, existing research on the relatedness and coherence motives has not tried, e.g., to assess whether our tendency to be motivated to agree with our friends is due to the fact that we want to be harmonious with our friends or due to the fact that we tend to trust our friends judgments in general. Nor has this research asked these people about their background beliefs, which, as we have seen, can be relevant for determining whether they are epistemically justified in their judgments or not. At the very least, it seems that future research in this area should control for these possibilities. Until then, it seems premature to claim that reasoning is biased and that the purpose of reasoning is to provide a biased basis for justification. 8. Conclusion 27

28 The relatedness and the coherence motives are Haidt s basis for believing that reasoning is biased. In this paper, I argued that Haidt simply assumes that the relatedness and coherence motives are biases. Drawing on the literature on epistemic justification, I showed that these motives are not always biases. Among other things, the relatedness motives need not be biases because we may have the tendency to be motivated to agree with our friends because we tend to trust our friends judgments in general, which can be an epistemically rational response. And, among other things, the coherence motives need not be biases because our epistemically justified background beliefs can play a significant role in determining the way we respond to new evidence. If this is correct, Haidt has not established that our reasoning is biased. If so, this also calls into question the aspect of the SIM, according to which the purpose of reasoning is to provide a biased basis for justification. And if all of this is right, it is premature to draw firm conclusions about how the SIM may undercut the evidential weight of our moral judgments. References Alston, W. P. 1985: Concepts of Epistemic Justification. Monist, 68, Bishop, M. A. and Trout, J. D. 2005: Epistemology and the psychology of human judgment, New York: Oxford University Press. Chaiken, S., Giner-Sorolla, R. and Chen, S. 1996: Beyond accuracy: Defense and impression motives in heuristic and systematic information processing. In Gollwitzer, P. M. and Bargh, J. A. (eds) The psychology of action: Linking cognition and motivation to behavior. New York: Guilford Press. 28

29 Chen, S., Shechter, D. and Chaiken, S. 1996: Getting at the truth or getting along: Accuracy- versus impression-motivated heuristic and systematic processing. Journal of Personality and Social Psychology, 71, Clarke, S. 2008: SIM and the City: Rationalism in Psychology and Philosophy of Haidt's Account of Moral Judgment. Philosophical Psychology, 21, Fine, C. 2006: Is the emotional dog wagging its rational tail, or chasing it? Philosophical Explorations, 9, Gibbard, A. 2008: Reconciling our aims: In search of bases for ethics, New York: Oxford University Press. Gigerenzer, G. and Todd, P. M. 1999: Simple Heuristics that Make Us Smart, Oxford: Oxford University Press. Greene, J. and Haidt, J. 2002: How (and where) does moral judgment work? Trends in Cognitive Sciences, 6, Haidt, J. 2001: The emotional dog and its rational tail: A social intuitionist approach to moral judgment. Psychological Review, 108, Haidt, J. 2003: The emotional dog does learn new tricks: A reply to Pizarro and Bloom. Psychological Review, 110, Haidt, J. 2006: The Happiness Hypothesis, London: Arrow Books. Haidt, J. 2007: The new synthesis in moral psychology. Science, 316, Haidt, J. and Bjorklund, F. 2007a: Social intuitionists answer six questions about moral psychology. In Sinnott-Armstrong, W. (ed) Moral psychology, Vol. 2: The cognitive science of morality: Intuition and diversity. Cambridge MA: MIT Press. 29

30 Haidt, J. and Bjorklund, F. 2007b: Social intuitionists reason, in conversation. In Sinnott- Armstrong, W. (ed) Moral psychology, Vol. 2: The cognitive science of morality: Intuition and diversity. Cambridge MA: MIT Press. Haidt, J., Bjorklund, F. and Murphy, S. 2000: Moral dumbfounding: When intuition finds no reason. Unpublished Manuscript. Haidt, J. and Hersh, M. A. 2001: Sexual morality: the cultures and emotions of conservatives and liberals. Journal of Applied Social Psychology, 31. Kennett, J. and Fine, C. 2009: Will the Real Moral Judgment Please Stand Up? Ethical Theory and Moral Practice, 12, Kerr, N. L., Maccoun, R. J. and Kramer, G. P. 1996: Bias in judgment: Comparing individuals and groups. Psychological Review, 103, Kohlberg, L. 1969: Stage and sequence: The cognitive-developmental approach to socialization. In Goslin, D. A. (ed) Handbook of socialization theory and research. Chicago: Rand McNally. Kunda, Z. and Sanitioso, R. 1989: Motivated changes in the self-concept. Journal of Experimental Social Psychology, 25, Levy, N. 2006: The wisdom of the pack. Philosophical explorations, 9, Lord, C. G., Ross, L. and Lepper, M. R. 1979: Biased assimilation and attitude polarization: The effects of prior theories on subsequently considered evidence. Journal of Personality and Social Psychology, 37, Mahoney, M. 1977: Publication prejudice: An experimental study of confirmatory bias in the peer review system. Cognitive Therapy and Research, 1,

PHIL 480: Seminar in the History of Philosophy Building Moral Character: Neo-Confucianism and Moral Psychology

PHIL 480: Seminar in the History of Philosophy Building Moral Character: Neo-Confucianism and Moral Psychology PHIL 480: Seminar in the History of Philosophy Building Moral Character: Neo-Confucianism and Moral Psychology Spring 2013 Professor JeeLoo Liu [Handout #12] Jonathan Haidt, The Emotional Dog and Its Rational

More information

Self-Evidence and A Priori Moral Knowledge

Self-Evidence and A Priori Moral Knowledge Self-Evidence and A Priori Moral Knowledge Colorado State University BIBLID [0873-626X (2012) 33; pp. 459-467] Abstract According to rationalists about moral knowledge, some moral truths are knowable a

More information

Skepticism and Internalism

Skepticism and Internalism Skepticism and Internalism John Greco Abstract: This paper explores a familiar skeptical problematic and considers some strategies for responding to it. Section 1 reconstructs and disambiguates the skeptical

More information

Huemer s Clarkeanism

Huemer s Clarkeanism Philosophy and Phenomenological Research Philosophy and Phenomenological Research Vol. LXXVIII No. 1, January 2009 Ó 2009 International Phenomenological Society Huemer s Clarkeanism mark schroeder University

More information

ALTERNATIVE SELF-DEFEAT ARGUMENTS: A REPLY TO MIZRAHI

ALTERNATIVE SELF-DEFEAT ARGUMENTS: A REPLY TO MIZRAHI ALTERNATIVE SELF-DEFEAT ARGUMENTS: A REPLY TO MIZRAHI Michael HUEMER ABSTRACT: I address Moti Mizrahi s objections to my use of the Self-Defeat Argument for Phenomenal Conservatism (PC). Mizrahi contends

More information

Robert Audi, The Architecture of Reason: The Structure and. Substance of Rationality. Oxford: Oxford University Press, Pp. xvi, 286.

Robert Audi, The Architecture of Reason: The Structure and. Substance of Rationality. Oxford: Oxford University Press, Pp. xvi, 286. Robert Audi, The Architecture of Reason: The Structure and Substance of Rationality. Oxford: Oxford University Press, 2001. Pp. xvi, 286. Reviewed by Gilbert Harman Princeton University August 19, 2002

More information

Review of Erik J. Wielenberg: Robust Ethics: The Metaphysics and Epistemology of Godless Normative Realism

Review of Erik J. Wielenberg: Robust Ethics: The Metaphysics and Epistemology of Godless Normative Realism 2015 by Centre for Ethics, KU Leuven This article may not exactly replicate the published version. It is not the copy of record. http://ethical-perspectives.be/ Ethical Perspectives 22 (3) For the published

More information

Pollock and Sturgeon on defeaters

Pollock and Sturgeon on defeaters University of Nebraska - Lincoln DigitalCommons@University of Nebraska - Lincoln Faculty Publications - Department of Philosophy Philosophy, Department of 2018 Pollock and Sturgeon on defeaters Albert

More information

From: Michael Huemer, Ethical Intuitionism (2005)

From: Michael Huemer, Ethical Intuitionism (2005) From: Michael Huemer, Ethical Intuitionism (2005) 214 L rsmkv!rs ks syxssm! finds Sally funny, but later decides he was mistaken about her funniness when the audience merely groans.) It seems, then, that

More information

Four Arguments that the Cognitive Psychology of Religion Undermines the Justification of Religious Belief

Four Arguments that the Cognitive Psychology of Religion Undermines the Justification of Religious Belief Four Arguments that the Cognitive Psychology of Religion Undermines the Justification of Religious Belief Michael J. Murray Over the last decade a handful of cognitive models of religious belief have begun

More information

THE TWO-DIMENSIONAL ARGUMENT AGAINST MATERIALISM AND ITS SEMANTIC PREMISE

THE TWO-DIMENSIONAL ARGUMENT AGAINST MATERIALISM AND ITS SEMANTIC PREMISE Diametros nr 29 (wrzesień 2011): 80-92 THE TWO-DIMENSIONAL ARGUMENT AGAINST MATERIALISM AND ITS SEMANTIC PREMISE Karol Polcyn 1. PRELIMINARIES Chalmers articulates his argument in terms of two-dimensional

More information

Bayesian Probability

Bayesian Probability Bayesian Probability Patrick Maher September 4, 2008 ABSTRACT. Bayesian decision theory is here construed as explicating a particular concept of rational choice and Bayesian probability is taken to be

More information

TWO ACCOUNTS OF THE NORMATIVITY OF RATIONALITY

TWO ACCOUNTS OF THE NORMATIVITY OF RATIONALITY DISCUSSION NOTE BY JONATHAN WAY JOURNAL OF ETHICS & SOCIAL PHILOSOPHY DISCUSSION NOTE DECEMBER 2009 URL: WWW.JESP.ORG COPYRIGHT JONATHAN WAY 2009 Two Accounts of the Normativity of Rationality RATIONALITY

More information

Moral Psych: W 18 February 27, Handout #3: Haidt s Two Systems View

Moral Psych: W 18 February 27, Handout #3: Haidt s Two Systems View Phil 134/ 234 G Prof. Aaron Z. Zimmerman Moral Psych: W 18 February 27, 2018 1. Characterizing the Opponent Handout #3: Haidt s Two Systems View The First Characterization: Haidt says that according to

More information

CRUCIAL TOPICS IN THE DEBATE ABOUT THE EXISTENCE OF EXTERNAL REASONS

CRUCIAL TOPICS IN THE DEBATE ABOUT THE EXISTENCE OF EXTERNAL REASONS CRUCIAL TOPICS IN THE DEBATE ABOUT THE EXISTENCE OF EXTERNAL REASONS By MARANATHA JOY HAYES A THESIS PRESENTED TO THE GRADUATE SCHOOL OF THE UNIVERSITY OF FLORIDA IN PARTIAL FULFILLMENT OF THE REQUIREMENTS

More information

Luck, Rationality, and Explanation: A Reply to Elga s Lucky to Be Rational. Joshua Schechter. Brown University

Luck, Rationality, and Explanation: A Reply to Elga s Lucky to Be Rational. Joshua Schechter. Brown University Luck, Rationality, and Explanation: A Reply to Elga s Lucky to Be Rational Joshua Schechter Brown University I Introduction What is the epistemic significance of discovering that one of your beliefs depends

More information

Deontological Perspectivism: A Reply to Lockie Hamid Vahid, Institute for Research in Fundamental Sciences, Tehran

Deontological Perspectivism: A Reply to Lockie Hamid Vahid, Institute for Research in Fundamental Sciences, Tehran Deontological Perspectivism: A Reply to Lockie Hamid Vahid, Institute for Research in Fundamental Sciences, Tehran Abstract In his (2015) paper, Robert Lockie seeks to add a contextualized, relativist

More information

ZAGZEBSKI ON RATIONALITY

ZAGZEBSKI ON RATIONALITY ZAGZEBSKI ON RATIONALITY DUNCAN PRITCHARD & SHANE RYAN University of Edinburgh Soochow University, Taipei INTRODUCTION 1 This paper examines Linda Zagzebski s (2012) account of rationality, as set out

More information

Varieties of Apriority

Varieties of Apriority S E V E N T H E X C U R S U S Varieties of Apriority T he notions of a priori knowledge and justification play a central role in this work. There are many ways in which one can understand the a priori,

More information

SCHAFFER S DEMON NATHAN BALLANTYNE AND IAN EVANS

SCHAFFER S DEMON NATHAN BALLANTYNE AND IAN EVANS SCHAFFER S DEMON by NATHAN BALLANTYNE AND IAN EVANS Abstract: Jonathan Schaffer (2010) has summoned a new sort of demon which he calls the debasing demon that apparently threatens all of our purported

More information

Stem Cell Research on Embryonic Persons is Just

Stem Cell Research on Embryonic Persons is Just Stem Cell Research on Embryonic Persons is Just Abstract: I argue that embryonic stem cell research is fair to the embryo even on the assumption that the embryo has attained full personhood and an attendant

More information

ELEONORE STUMP PENELHUM ON SKEPTICS AND FIDEISTS

ELEONORE STUMP PENELHUM ON SKEPTICS AND FIDEISTS ELEONORE STUMP PENELHUM ON SKEPTICS AND FIDEISTS ABSTRACT. Professor Penelhum has argued that there is a common error about the history of skepticism and that the exposure of this error would significantly

More information

DO WE NEED A THEORY OF METAPHYSICAL COMPOSITION?

DO WE NEED A THEORY OF METAPHYSICAL COMPOSITION? 1 DO WE NEED A THEORY OF METAPHYSICAL COMPOSITION? ROBERT C. OSBORNE DRAFT (02/27/13) PLEASE DO NOT CITE WITHOUT PERMISSION I. Introduction Much of the recent work in contemporary metaphysics has been

More information

Common Morality: Deciding What to Do 1

Common Morality: Deciding What to Do 1 Common Morality: Deciding What to Do 1 By Bernard Gert (1934-2011) [Page 15] Analogy between Morality and Grammar Common morality is complex, but it is less complex than the grammar of a language. Just

More information

A solution to the problem of hijacked experience

A solution to the problem of hijacked experience A solution to the problem of hijacked experience Jill is not sure what Jack s current mood is, but she fears that he is angry with her. Then Jack steps into the room. Jill gets a good look at his face.

More information

Explanatory Indispensability and Deliberative Indispensability: Against Enoch s Analogy Alex Worsnip University of North Carolina at Chapel Hill

Explanatory Indispensability and Deliberative Indispensability: Against Enoch s Analogy Alex Worsnip University of North Carolina at Chapel Hill Explanatory Indispensability and Deliberative Indispensability: Against Enoch s Analogy Alex Worsnip University of North Carolina at Chapel Hill Forthcoming in Thought please cite published version In

More information

Gale on a Pragmatic Argument for Religious Belief

Gale on a Pragmatic Argument for Religious Belief Volume 6, Number 1 Gale on a Pragmatic Argument for Religious Belief by Philip L. Quinn Abstract: This paper is a study of a pragmatic argument for belief in the existence of God constructed and criticized

More information

Philosophical Perspectives, 16, Language and Mind, 2002 THE AIM OF BELIEF 1. Ralph Wedgwood Merton College, Oxford

Philosophical Perspectives, 16, Language and Mind, 2002 THE AIM OF BELIEF 1. Ralph Wedgwood Merton College, Oxford Philosophical Perspectives, 16, Language and Mind, 2002 THE AIM OF BELIEF 1 Ralph Wedgwood Merton College, Oxford 0. Introduction It is often claimed that beliefs aim at the truth. Indeed, this claim has

More information

Experience and Foundationalism in Audi s The Architecture of Reason

Experience and Foundationalism in Audi s The Architecture of Reason Philosophy and Phenomenological Research Vol. LXVII, No. 1, July 2003 Experience and Foundationalism in Audi s The Architecture of Reason WALTER SINNOTT-ARMSTRONG Dartmouth College Robert Audi s The Architecture

More information

Reliabilism and the Problem of Defeaters

Reliabilism and the Problem of Defeaters Reliabilism and the Problem of Defeaters Prof. Dr. Thomas Grundmann Philosophisches Seminar Universität zu Köln Albertus Magnus Platz 50923 Köln E-mail: thomas.grundmann@uni-koeln.de 4.454 words Reliabilism

More information

Ethical non-naturalism

Ethical non-naturalism Michael Lacewing Ethical non-naturalism Ethical non-naturalism is usually understood as a form of cognitivist moral realism. So we first need to understand what cognitivism and moral realism is before

More information

Testimony and Moral Understanding Anthony T. Flood, Ph.D. Introduction

Testimony and Moral Understanding Anthony T. Flood, Ph.D. Introduction 24 Testimony and Moral Understanding Anthony T. Flood, Ph.D. Abstract: In this paper, I address Linda Zagzebski s analysis of the relation between moral testimony and understanding arguing that Aquinas

More information

What Is Moral Reasoning?

What Is Moral Reasoning? Seattle Pacific University Digital Commons @ SPU SPU Works January 1st, 2015 What Is Moral Reasoning? Leland F. Saunders Follow this and additional works at: http://digitalcommons.spu.edu/works Part of

More information

Is there a good epistemological argument against platonism? DAVID LIGGINS

Is there a good epistemological argument against platonism? DAVID LIGGINS [This is the penultimate draft of an article that appeared in Analysis 66.2 (April 2006), 135-41, available here by permission of Analysis, the Analysis Trust, and Blackwell Publishing. The definitive

More information

Against Coherence: Truth, Probability, and Justification. Erik J. Olsson. Oxford: Oxford University Press, Pp. xiii, 232.

Against Coherence: Truth, Probability, and Justification. Erik J. Olsson. Oxford: Oxford University Press, Pp. xiii, 232. Against Coherence: Page 1 To appear in Philosophy and Phenomenological Research Against Coherence: Truth, Probability, and Justification. Erik J. Olsson. Oxford: Oxford University Press, 2005. Pp. xiii,

More information

A CONSEQUENTIALIST RESPONSE TO THE DEMANDINGNESS OBJECTION Nicholas R. Baker, Lee University THE DEMANDS OF ACT CONSEQUENTIALISM

A CONSEQUENTIALIST RESPONSE TO THE DEMANDINGNESS OBJECTION Nicholas R. Baker, Lee University THE DEMANDS OF ACT CONSEQUENTIALISM 1 A CONSEQUENTIALIST RESPONSE TO THE DEMANDINGNESS OBJECTION Nicholas R. Baker, Lee University INTRODUCTION We usually believe that morality has limits; that is, that there is some limit to what morality

More information

The Oxford Handbook of Epistemology

The Oxford Handbook of Epistemology Oxford Scholarship Online You are looking at 1-10 of 21 items for: booktitle : handbook phimet The Oxford Handbook of Epistemology Paul K. Moser (ed.) Item type: book DOI: 10.1093/0195130057.001.0001 This

More information

Scanlon on Double Effect

Scanlon on Double Effect Scanlon on Double Effect RALPH WEDGWOOD Merton College, University of Oxford In this new book Moral Dimensions, T. M. Scanlon (2008) explores the ethical significance of the intentions and motives with

More information

INTUITION AND CONSCIOUS REASONING

INTUITION AND CONSCIOUS REASONING The Philosophical Quarterly Vol. 63, No. 253 October 2013 ISSN 0031-8094 doi: 10.1111/1467-9213.12071 INTUITION AND CONSCIOUS REASONING BY OLE KOKSVIK This paper argues that, contrary to common opinion,

More information

THE SENSE OF FREEDOM 1. Dana K. Nelkin. I. Introduction. abandon even in the face of powerful arguments that this sense is illusory.

THE SENSE OF FREEDOM 1. Dana K. Nelkin. I. Introduction. abandon even in the face of powerful arguments that this sense is illusory. THE SENSE OF FREEDOM 1 Dana K. Nelkin I. Introduction We appear to have an inescapable sense that we are free, a sense that we cannot abandon even in the face of powerful arguments that this sense is illusory.

More information

3. Knowledge and Justification

3. Knowledge and Justification THE PROBLEMS OF KNOWLEDGE 11 3. Knowledge and Justification We have been discussing the role of skeptical arguments in epistemology and have already made some progress in thinking about reasoning and belief.

More information

The Many Problems of Memory Knowledge (Short Version)

The Many Problems of Memory Knowledge (Short Version) The Many Problems of Memory Knowledge (Short Version) Prepared For: The 13 th Annual Jakobsen Conference Abstract: Michael Huemer attempts to answer the question of when S remembers that P, what kind of

More information

Sentence Starters from They Say, I Say

Sentence Starters from They Say, I Say Sentence Starters from They Say, I Say Introducing What They Say A number of have recently suggested that. It has become common today to dismiss. In their recent work, Y and Z have offered harsh critiques

More information

Reliabilism: Holistic or Simple?

Reliabilism: Holistic or Simple? Reliabilism: Holistic or Simple? Jeff Dunn jeffreydunn@depauw.edu 1 Introduction A standard statement of Reliabilism about justification goes something like this: Simple (Process) Reliabilism: S s believing

More information

On Dogramaci. Social Epistemology Review and Reply Collective, 2015 Vol. 4, No. 4,

On Dogramaci. Social Epistemology Review and Reply Collective, 2015 Vol. 4, No. 4, Epistemic Evaluations: Consequences, Costs and Benefits Peter Graham, Zachary Bachman, Meredith McFadden and Megan Stotts University of California, Riverside It is our pleasure to contribute to a discussion

More information

DESIRES AND BELIEFS OF ONE S OWN. Geoffrey Sayre-McCord and Michael Smith

DESIRES AND BELIEFS OF ONE S OWN. Geoffrey Sayre-McCord and Michael Smith Draft only. Please do not copy or cite without permission. DESIRES AND BELIEFS OF ONE S OWN Geoffrey Sayre-McCord and Michael Smith Much work in recent moral psychology attempts to spell out what it is

More information

KNOWLEDGE ON AFFECTIVE TRUST. Arnon Keren

KNOWLEDGE ON AFFECTIVE TRUST. Arnon Keren Abstracta SPECIAL ISSUE VI, pp. 33 46, 2012 KNOWLEDGE ON AFFECTIVE TRUST Arnon Keren Epistemologists of testimony widely agree on the fact that our reliance on other people's testimony is extensive. However,

More information

Phenomenal Conservatism and the Internalist Intuition

Phenomenal Conservatism and the Internalist Intuition [Published in American Philosophical Quarterly 43 (2006): 147-58. Official version: http://www.jstor.org/stable/20010233.] Phenomenal Conservatism and the Internalist Intuition ABSTRACT: Externalist theories

More information

Why Is Epistemic Evaluation Prescriptive?

Why Is Epistemic Evaluation Prescriptive? Why Is Epistemic Evaluation Prescriptive? Kate Nolfi UNC Chapel Hill (Forthcoming in Inquiry, Special Issue on the Nature of Belief, edited by Susanna Siegel) Abstract Epistemic evaluation is often appropriately

More information

CONSCIOUSNESS, INTENTIONALITY AND CONCEPTS: REPLY TO NELKIN

CONSCIOUSNESS, INTENTIONALITY AND CONCEPTS: REPLY TO NELKIN ----------------------------------------------------------------- PSYCHE: AN INTERDISCIPLINARY JOURNAL OF RESEARCH ON CONSCIOUSNESS ----------------------------------------------------------------- CONSCIOUSNESS,

More information

Comment on Robert Audi, Democratic Authority and the Separation of Church and State

Comment on Robert Audi, Democratic Authority and the Separation of Church and State Weithman 1. Comment on Robert Audi, Democratic Authority and the Separation of Church and State Among the tasks of liberal democratic theory are the identification and defense of political principles that

More information

Epistemic Responsibility in Science

Epistemic Responsibility in Science Epistemic Responsibility in Science Haixin Dang had27@pitt.edu Social Epistemology Networking Event Oslo May 24, 2018 I Motivating the problem Examples: - Observation of Top Quark Production in p p Collisions

More information

PHL340 Handout 8: Evaluating Dogmatism

PHL340 Handout 8: Evaluating Dogmatism PHL340 Handout 8: Evaluating Dogmatism 1 Dogmatism Last class we looked at Jim Pryor s paper on dogmatism about perceptual justification (for background on the notion of justification, see the handout

More information

EXTERNALISM AND THE CONTENT OF MORAL MOTIVATION

EXTERNALISM AND THE CONTENT OF MORAL MOTIVATION EXTERNALISM AND THE CONTENT OF MORAL MOTIVATION Caj Strandberg Department of Philosophy, Lund University and Gothenburg University Caj.Strandberg@fil.lu.se ABSTRACT: Michael Smith raises in his fetishist

More information

PHILOSOPHY OF LANGUAGE AND META-ETHICS

PHILOSOPHY OF LANGUAGE AND META-ETHICS The Philosophical Quarterly, Vol. 54, No. 217 October 2004 ISSN 0031 8094 PHILOSOPHY OF LANGUAGE AND META-ETHICS BY IRA M. SCHNALL Meta-ethical discussions commonly distinguish subjectivism from emotivism,

More information

LODGE VEGAS # 32 ON EDUCATION

LODGE VEGAS # 32 ON EDUCATION Wisdom First published Mon Jan 8, 2007 LODGE VEGAS # 32 ON EDUCATION The word philosophy means love of wisdom. What is wisdom? What is this thing that philosophers love? Some of the systematic philosophers

More information

Are There Reasons to Be Rational?

Are There Reasons to Be Rational? Are There Reasons to Be Rational? Olav Gjelsvik, University of Oslo The thesis. Among people writing about rationality, few people are more rational than Wlodek Rabinowicz. But are there reasons for being

More information

Hilary Kornblith, Distrusting Reason

Hilary Kornblith, Distrusting Reason Hilary Kornblith, Distrusting Reason The activity of reason-giving is an important part of our intellectual lives. At times, we offer reasons to justify our actions or our beliefs, both to others and to

More information

Belief Ownership without Authorship: Agent Reliabilism s Unlucky Gambit against Reflective Luck Benjamin Bayer September 1 st, 2014

Belief Ownership without Authorship: Agent Reliabilism s Unlucky Gambit against Reflective Luck Benjamin Bayer September 1 st, 2014 Belief Ownership without Authorship: Agent Reliabilism s Unlucky Gambit against Reflective Luck Benjamin Bayer September 1 st, 2014 Abstract: This paper examines a persuasive attempt to defend reliabilist

More information

Received: 30 August 2007 / Accepted: 16 November 2007 / Published online: 28 December 2007 # Springer Science + Business Media B.V.

Received: 30 August 2007 / Accepted: 16 November 2007 / Published online: 28 December 2007 # Springer Science + Business Media B.V. Acta anal. (2007) 22:267 279 DOI 10.1007/s12136-007-0012-y What Is Entitlement? Albert Casullo Received: 30 August 2007 / Accepted: 16 November 2007 / Published online: 28 December 2007 # Springer Science

More information

Keywords precise, imprecise, sharp, mushy, credence, subjective, probability, reflection, Bayesian, epistemology

Keywords precise, imprecise, sharp, mushy, credence, subjective, probability, reflection, Bayesian, epistemology Coin flips, credences, and the Reflection Principle * BRETT TOPEY Abstract One recent topic of debate in Bayesian epistemology has been the question of whether imprecise credences can be rational. I argue

More information

what makes reasons sufficient?

what makes reasons sufficient? Mark Schroeder University of Southern California August 2, 2010 what makes reasons sufficient? This paper addresses the question: what makes reasons sufficient? and offers the answer, being at least as

More information

Moral Psych: S 17 May 14, Handout #3: Haidt s Two Systems View

Moral Psych: S 17 May 14, Handout #3: Haidt s Two Systems View Phil 134/ 234 G Prof. Aaron Z. Zimmerman Moral Psych: S 17 May 14, 2017 1. Characterizing the Opponent Handout #3: Haidt s Two Systems View The First Characterization: Haidt says that according to rationalist

More information

Attraction, Description, and the Desire-Satisfaction Theory of Welfare

Attraction, Description, and the Desire-Satisfaction Theory of Welfare Attraction, Description, and the Desire-Satisfaction Theory of Welfare The desire-satisfaction theory of welfare says that what is basically good for a subject what benefits him in the most fundamental,

More information

The unity of the normative

The unity of the normative The unity of the normative The Harvard community has made this article openly available. Please share how this access benefits you. Your story matters Citation Scanlon, T. M. 2011. The Unity of the Normative.

More information

Understanding and its Relation to Knowledge Christoph Baumberger, ETH Zurich & University of Zurich

Understanding and its Relation to Knowledge Christoph Baumberger, ETH Zurich & University of Zurich Understanding and its Relation to Knowledge Christoph Baumberger, ETH Zurich & University of Zurich christoph.baumberger@env.ethz.ch Abstract: Is understanding the same as or at least a species of knowledge?

More information

Phenomenal Consciousness and Intentionality<1>

Phenomenal Consciousness and Intentionality<1> Phenomenal Consciousness and Intentionality Dana K. Nelkin Department of Philosophy Florida State University Tallahassee, FL 32303 U.S.A. dnelkin@mailer.fsu.edu Copyright (c) Dana Nelkin 2001 PSYCHE,

More information

the negative reason existential fallacy

the negative reason existential fallacy Mark Schroeder University of Southern California May 21, 2007 the negative reason existential fallacy 1 There is a very common form of argument in moral philosophy nowadays, and it goes like this: P1 It

More information

A Brief History of Thinking about Thinking Thomas Lombardo

A Brief History of Thinking about Thinking Thomas Lombardo A Brief History of Thinking about Thinking Thomas Lombardo "Education is nothing more nor less than learning to think." Peter Facione In this article I review the historical evolution of principles and

More information

2014 THE BIBLIOGRAPHIA ISSN: Online First: 21 October 2014

2014 THE BIBLIOGRAPHIA ISSN: Online First: 21 October 2014 PROBABILITY IN THE PHILOSOPHY OF RELIGION. Edited by Jake Chandler & Victoria S. Harrison. Oxford: Oxford University Press, 2012. Pp. 272. Hard Cover 42, ISBN: 978-0-19-960476-0. IN ADDITION TO AN INTRODUCTORY

More information

Henrik Ahlenius Department of Philosophy ETHICS & RESEARCH

Henrik Ahlenius Department of Philosophy ETHICS & RESEARCH Henrik Ahlenius Department of Philosophy henrik.ahlenius@philosophy.su.se ETHICS & RESEARCH Why a course like this? Tell you what the rules are Tell you to follow these rules Tell you to follow some other

More information

Direct Realism and the Brain-in-a-Vat Argument by Michael Huemer (2000)

Direct Realism and the Brain-in-a-Vat Argument by Michael Huemer (2000) Direct Realism and the Brain-in-a-Vat Argument by Michael Huemer (2000) One of the advantages traditionally claimed for direct realist theories of perception over indirect realist theories is that the

More information

Mark Schroeder. Slaves of the Passions. Melissa Barry Hume Studies Volume 36, Number 2 (2010), 225-228. Your use of the HUME STUDIES archive indicates your acceptance of HUME STUDIES Terms and Conditions

More information

Lost in Transmission: Testimonial Justification and Practical Reason

Lost in Transmission: Testimonial Justification and Practical Reason Lost in Transmission: Testimonial Justification and Practical Reason Andrew Peet and Eli Pitcovski Abstract Transmission views of testimony hold that the epistemic state of a speaker can, in some robust

More information

Oxford Scholarship Online Abstracts and Keywords

Oxford Scholarship Online Abstracts and Keywords Oxford Scholarship Online Abstracts and Keywords ISBN 9780198802693 Title The Value of Rationality Author(s) Ralph Wedgwood Book abstract Book keywords Rationality is a central concept for epistemology,

More information

Unit VI: Davidson and the interpretational approach to thought and language

Unit VI: Davidson and the interpretational approach to thought and language Unit VI: Davidson and the interpretational approach to thought and language October 29, 2003 1 Davidson s interdependence thesis..................... 1 2 Davidson s arguments for interdependence................

More information

Max Deutsch: The Myth of the Intuitive: Experimental Philosophy and Philosophical Method. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press, xx pp.

Max Deutsch: The Myth of the Intuitive: Experimental Philosophy and Philosophical Method. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press, xx pp. Max Deutsch: The Myth of the Intuitive: Experimental Philosophy and Philosophical Method. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press, 2015. 194+xx pp. This engaging and accessible book offers a spirited defence of armchair

More information

Kelly and McDowell on Perceptual Content. Fred Ablondi Department of Philosophy Hendrix College

Kelly and McDowell on Perceptual Content. Fred Ablondi Department of Philosophy Hendrix College Kelly and McDowell on Perceptual Content 1 Fred Ablondi Department of Philosophy Hendrix College (ablondi@mercury.hendrix.edu) [0] In a recent issue of EJAP, Sean Kelly [1998] defended the position that

More information

Epistemic Contextualism as a Theory of Primary Speaker Meaning

Epistemic Contextualism as a Theory of Primary Speaker Meaning Epistemic Contextualism as a Theory of Primary Speaker Meaning Gilbert Harman, Princeton University June 30, 2006 Jason Stanley s Knowledge and Practical Interests is a brilliant book, combining insights

More information

Philosophy Of Science On The Moral Neutrality Of Scientific Acceptance

Philosophy Of Science On The Moral Neutrality Of Scientific Acceptance University of Nebraska - Lincoln DigitalCommons@University of Nebraska - Lincoln Transactions of the Nebraska Academy of Sciences and Affiliated Societies Nebraska Academy of Sciences 1982 Philosophy Of

More information

What Should We Believe?

What Should We Believe? 1 What Should We Believe? Thomas Kelly, University of Notre Dame James Pryor, Princeton University Blackwell Publishers Consider the following question: What should I believe? This question is a normative

More information

1 Hans Jonas, The Imperative of Responsibility: In Search of an Ethics for the Technological Age (Chicago: University of Chicago Press, 1984), 1-10.

1 Hans Jonas, The Imperative of Responsibility: In Search of an Ethics for the Technological Age (Chicago: University of Chicago Press, 1984), 1-10. Introduction This book seeks to provide a metaethical analysis of the responsibility ethics of two of its prominent defenders: H. Richard Niebuhr and Emmanuel Levinas. In any ethical writings, some use

More information

Moral Relativism and Conceptual Analysis. David J. Chalmers

Moral Relativism and Conceptual Analysis. David J. Chalmers Moral Relativism and Conceptual Analysis David J. Chalmers An Inconsistent Triad (1) All truths are a priori entailed by fundamental truths (2) No moral truths are a priori entailed by fundamental truths

More information

THE UNIVERSITY OF WESTERN ONTARIO DEPARTMENT OF PHILOSOPHY Undergraduate Course Outline PHIL3501G: Epistemology

THE UNIVERSITY OF WESTERN ONTARIO DEPARTMENT OF PHILOSOPHY Undergraduate Course Outline PHIL3501G: Epistemology THE UNIVERSITY OF WESTERN ONTARIO DEPARTMENT OF PHILOSOPHY Undergraduate Course Outline 2016 PHIL3501G: Epistemology Winter Term 2016 Tues. 1:30-2:30 p.m. Thursday 1:30-3:30 p.m. Location: TBA Instructor:

More information

Theories of epistemic justification can be divided into two groups: internalist and

Theories of epistemic justification can be divided into two groups: internalist and 1 Internalism and externalism about justification Theories of epistemic justification can be divided into two groups: internalist and externalist. Internalist theories of justification say that whatever

More information

632 Ethics April 2014

632 Ethics April 2014 632 Ethics April 2014 Kornblith, Hilary. On Reflection. Oxford: Oxford University Press, 2012. Pp. 192. $45.00 ðclothþ. I. ON REFLECTION Hilary Kornblith thinks that reflection is overrated. His is the

More information

In Defense of Pure Reason: A Rationalist Account of A Priori Justification, by Laurence BonJour. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press,

In Defense of Pure Reason: A Rationalist Account of A Priori Justification, by Laurence BonJour. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, Book Reviews 1 In Defense of Pure Reason: A Rationalist Account of A Priori Justification, by Laurence BonJour. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1998. Pp. xiv + 232. H/b 37.50, $54.95, P/b 13.95,

More information

Wolterstorff on Divine Commands (part 1)

Wolterstorff on Divine Commands (part 1) Wolterstorff on Divine Commands (part 1) Glenn Peoples Page 1 of 10 Introduction Nicholas Wolterstorff, in his masterful work Justice: Rights and Wrongs, presents an account of justice in terms of inherent

More information

Non-evidential believing and permissivism about evidence: A reply to Dan-Johan Eklund

Non-evidential believing and permissivism about evidence: A reply to Dan-Johan Eklund Non-evidential believing and permissivism about evidence: A reply to Dan-Johan Eklund JOSHUA COCKAYNE Department of Philosophy, University of York, York, YO10 5DD, UK jlc513@york.ac.uk DAVID EFIRD Department

More information

A Review of Neil Feit s Belief about the Self

A Review of Neil Feit s Belief about the Self A Review of Neil Feit s Belief about the Self Stephan Torre 1 Neil Feit. Belief about the Self. Oxford GB: Oxford University Press 2008. 216 pages. Belief about the Self is a clearly written, engaging

More information

Adapted from The Academic Essay: A Brief Anatomy, for the Writing Center at Harvard University by Gordon Harvey. Counter-Argument

Adapted from The Academic Essay: A Brief Anatomy, for the Writing Center at Harvard University by Gordon Harvey. Counter-Argument Adapted from The Academic Essay: A Brief Anatomy, for the Writing Center at Harvard University by Gordon Harvey Counter-Argument When you write an academic essay, you make an argument: you propose a thesis

More information

DEFEASIBLE A PRIORI JUSTIFICATION: A REPLY TO THUROW

DEFEASIBLE A PRIORI JUSTIFICATION: A REPLY TO THUROW The Philosophical Quarterly Vol. 58, No. 231 April 2008 ISSN 0031 8094 doi: 10.1111/j.1467-9213.2007.512.x DEFEASIBLE A PRIORI JUSTIFICATION: A REPLY TO THUROW BY ALBERT CASULLO Joshua Thurow offers a

More information

Goldman on Knowledge as True Belief. Alvin Goldman (2002a, 183) distinguishes the following four putative uses or senses of

Goldman on Knowledge as True Belief. Alvin Goldman (2002a, 183) distinguishes the following four putative uses or senses of Goldman on Knowledge as True Belief Alvin Goldman (2002a, 183) distinguishes the following four putative uses or senses of knowledge : (1) Knowledge = belief (2) Knowledge = institutionalized belief (3)

More information

Utilitarianism: For and Against (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1973), pp Reprinted in Moral Luck (CUP, 1981).

Utilitarianism: For and Against (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1973), pp Reprinted in Moral Luck (CUP, 1981). Draft of 3-21- 13 PHIL 202: Core Ethics; Winter 2013 Core Sequence in the History of Ethics, 2011-2013 IV: 19 th and 20 th Century Moral Philosophy David O. Brink Handout #14: Williams, Internalism, and

More information

Huemer s Problem of Memory Knowledge

Huemer s Problem of Memory Knowledge Huemer s Problem of Memory Knowledge ABSTRACT: When S seems to remember that P, what kind of justification does S have for believing that P? In "The Problem of Memory Knowledge." Michael Huemer offers

More information

Rationalism. A. He, like others at the time, was obsessed with questions of truth and doubt

Rationalism. A. He, like others at the time, was obsessed with questions of truth and doubt Rationalism I. Descartes (1596-1650) A. He, like others at the time, was obsessed with questions of truth and doubt 1. How could one be certain in the absence of religious guidance and trustworthy senses

More information

Theoretical Virtues in Science

Theoretical Virtues in Science manuscript, September 11, 2017 Samuel K. Schindler Theoretical Virtues in Science Uncovering Reality Through Theory Table of contents Table of Figures... iii Introduction... 1 1 Theoretical virtues, truth,

More information

Does the Skeptic Win? A Defense of Moore. I. Moorean Methodology. In A Proof of the External World, Moore argues as follows:

Does the Skeptic Win? A Defense of Moore. I. Moorean Methodology. In A Proof of the External World, Moore argues as follows: Does the Skeptic Win? A Defense of Moore I argue that Moore s famous response to the skeptic should be accepted even by the skeptic. My paper has three main stages. First, I will briefly outline G. E.

More information

What Lurks Beneath the Integrity Objection. Bernard Williams s alienation and integrity arguments against consequentialism have

What Lurks Beneath the Integrity Objection. Bernard Williams s alienation and integrity arguments against consequentialism have What Lurks Beneath the Integrity Objection Bernard Williams s alienation and integrity arguments against consequentialism have served as the point of departure for much of the most interesting work that

More information

Divine omniscience, timelessness, and the power to do otherwise

Divine omniscience, timelessness, and the power to do otherwise Religious Studies 42, 123 139 f 2006 Cambridge University Press doi:10.1017/s0034412506008250 Printed in the United Kingdom Divine omniscience, timelessness, and the power to do otherwise HUGH RICE Christ

More information