What Numbers Might Be Scott Soames. John's anti-nominalism embraces numbers without, as far as I know, worrying very

Size: px
Start display at page:

Download "What Numbers Might Be Scott Soames. John's anti-nominalism embraces numbers without, as far as I know, worrying very"

Transcription

1 What Numbers Might Be Scott Soames John's anti-nominalism embraces numbers without, as far as I know, worrying very much about whether they fall under some other category like sets or properties. His strongest reason for embracing them is sound; our most advanced, reliable, and systematic knowledge-generating practices, mathematics and natural science, tell us that there are numbers, along with sets, functions, and so on. We also have reliable sources of knowledge testifying to the existence of other things -- expression types, languages, act and event types, properties, colors, shapes, species, and natural kinds in general -- about which some of the worries raised about numbers also arise. Still numbers have been the prominent targets of philosophers who are reluctant to grant the existence of anything beyond concrete particulars. John isn't sympathetic, nor am I. I sense that he also isn't too worried about trying to determine precisely what natural or other numbers are. If not, the reason may be that nothing in mathematics or natural science, requires, or even strongly favors, one proposed identification of natural numbers over another. So if none is needed, why bother? Certainly, none is needed to avoid skepticism. Still, we may want to know What explains our knowledge of numbers? -- all the way down to the knowledge children gain when they learn to count. Philosophical questions about how we know about all sorts of things can be puzzling, and ought to be pursued. But our knowledge of numbers seems to generate a special puzzlement not generated by our knowledge of rocks and trees. In part this is because our knowledge of the latter is largely perceptual whereas our knowledge of numbers is not generally thought of in this way. Outside of attempts to explain why there is no basis for radical skepticism about knowledge of the so-called external world,

2 philosophers haven't been overly perplexed by the idea that we know that there are mountains. But apart from Penny Maddy, who has argued that certain sets, the members of which can be seen, can also, themselves, be seen, most philosophers seem to take it for granted that we can't see sets or numbers. Even if we could see some sets, we surely can't see them all, and the usual constraints for evaluating different set-theoretic conceptions of natural numbers don't discriminate among them in that way. It is against this background that explaining our knowledge of natural numbers may worth special attention. Frege's idea, that we can find out what numbers are by finding out what best explains our knowledge of them, remains compelling. In sections 58 and 60 of The Foundations of Arithmetic, he says that nothing we can picture or imagine seems to be an apt candidate for being the number 4. But he is not deterred. Although we can, in his words, form no idea of the content of a number term, he insists that this no reason for denying that it does have content. Rather than considering the term in isolation, he thinks we should ask what it contributes to meaningful sentences in which it appears. He admonishes us "Always to keep before our eyes a complete proposition [he means 'sentence']. Only [he says] in a proposition have the words really a meaning." Although I like his emphasis on complete sentences, I would supplement his enigmatic "context principle" with a related, though perhaps equally enigmatic, principle: Natural numbers are whatever they have to be in order to explain our knowledge of them. There are lots of sentences containing numerical terms occurring as proper names, adjectives, or stand-alone predicates that express propositions we know. The strategy for finding out what natural numbers are is to investigate which assignments of meanings and referents to these terms best advances our ability to explain our knowledge of the truth of the propositions expressed by numerical sentences. 2

3 By 'our knowledge', I mean everyone's knowledge -- children who know only a little, adults who know more, and elementary number theorists who know much more. I presume that this vast population shares a fair bit of common knowledge, even though some know a great deal more than others. Assuming, as we must, that no one knows all arithmetical truths -- or even any set of truths from which all others could be validly derived -- the resulting assignment of true propositions to arithmetical sentences will outstrip all actual arithmetical knowledge. Still, we should be able to explain various possible extensions of the knowledge we now posses. I am most interested in explaining (i) how we achieve any knowledge of numbers at all, and (ii) how, with a little instruction, we acquire more knowledge by learning one or another set of arithmetical axioms, and/or convenient calculation procedures. Mainly, I am interested in what a realistic starting point for our arithmetical knowledge might look like. I suspect that one component of that starting point is what Frege called Hume s Principle, which specifies that the number of X s is the same as the number of Y s if and only if the X s and Y s can be exhaustively paired off (without remainder). As it happens, the number of universities at which I have been a regular faculty member -- Yale, Princeton, and USC -- can be exhaustively paired off (without remainder) with the fingers I am holding up now. So, the number of universities at which I have served is the same the number as the number of fingers I am holding up. Both the fingers and the universities are three (in number). What is this property, being three (in number), predicated of? It s not predicated of any of my past faculty homes; neither Yale, Princeton, nor USC, is three (in number). It is also not predicated of the set that contains them (and only them); since the set of those universities is a single thing, it s not three either. Like the property being scattered, the property being three (in number) is irreducibly plural. It is a property that applies, not to any 3

4 single instance of any type of thing (simple, composite, concrete, or abstract), but to multiple things of a given type considered together. My former Ph.D. students are scattered around the world, even though no one of them is scattered around the world, and the set containing them isn t scattered around the world either. With this in mind, consider the hypothesis that each natural number N greater than or equal to 2 is the plural property being N (in number), and that the number 1 is a property applying to each individual thing considered on its own. Zero is a property that doesn't 1 apply to anything, or to any things. Suppose then that natural numbers are cardinality properties of individuals and multiples of the kind just illustrated. How do we gain knowledge of them? In the beginning, we do so by counting. Imagine a child inferring that I am holding up three fingers from her perceptual knowledge that x, y, and z are different fingers. Having learned to count -- at first by memorizing a sequence of verbal numerals -- she concludes that the fingers are three in number, which is a property she has learned to recognize from other events of counting things of various types. In so doing, she pairs off, without remainder, the fingers I am holding up with the English words one, 'two, and three, thereby ensuring that the fingers and the numerals have the same number in Frege s sense. Even better, the number they share is designated by the numeral, three, that ends the count; it is the property being three (in number). With this, we have the germ of an idea that combines the best of the attempted Frege-Russell reductions with a striking, but flawed and incompletely developed insight gestured at in section 1 of Wittgenstein's Philosophical Investigations. The book begins with a quotation from Augustine. 1 This way of thinking of natural numbers grows out of two path-breaking articles one, Boolos (1984) -- by my former teacher, George Boolos, and the other -- Arabic Numerals and the Problem of Mathematical Sophistication, forthcoming by my former Ph.D. student Mario Gomez Torrente. 4

5 When they (my elders) named some object, and accordingly moved toward something, I saw this and I grasped that the thing was called by the sound they uttered when they meant to point it out. Their intention was shown by their bodily movements, as it were the natural language of all peoples: the expression of the face, the play of the eyes, the movement of other parts of the body, and the tone of voice, which expresses our state of mind in seeking, having, rejecting, or avoiding something. Thus, as I heard the words repeatedly used in their proper places in various sentences, I gradually learnt to understand what objects they signified. Wittgenstein uses the passage to illustrate a general conception of language he rejects -- a conception according to which the essence of all meaning is naming. One reason he rejects this conception involves an imagined priority in introducing words into a language, and in learning a language once the words have been introduced. The priority is one in which first comes our awareness of things in the world, then comes our decision to introduce certain words to talk about those things. In learning a language, we first focus on various candidates for what our elders are using a word to name, and then, having done so, we converge on the single candidate that best makes sense of the sentences they use containing the name we are trying to learn. Having set up the general picture he wants to reject, he immediately jumps to a use of language that, he thinks, doesn't conform to the picture. He says Now think of the following use of language: I send someone shopping. I give him a slip marked five red apples [On finding the apple drawer the shopkeeper] says the series of cardinal numbers--i assume that he knows them by heart--up to the word five and for each number he takes an apple of the same color as the sample out of the drawer. It is in this and similar ways that one operates with words But how does he know what he is to do with the word five? [W]hat is the meaning of the word five?--- No such thing was in question here, only how the word five is used. (PI section 1) This emphasis on the use of the numeral 'five', rather than its referent, is, I think, illuminating. But the lesson isn t that its meaning is its use; the meaning of the numeral 'five', which is also its referent, is the property being five in number, which isn t a use of anything. The proper lesson is that our use of the numeral in counting makes us aware of the property, which, as a result, becomes cognitively associated with the numeral, rather 5

6 than our antecedent non-linguistic recognition of the property making it available for naming. First the use, leading to the awareness of something to be named; not first the mystical awareness of number, and then the decision to name it. The importance of counting, which the passage from Wittgenstein emphasizes, is in establishing an epistemic foothold on a vast domain that none of us, individually or collectively, will ever actually count. Pretty much all of us know what we would have to do to count up to a trillion. But some of us don't know a verbal numeral in English for the number that comes after nine hundred ninety nine trillion, nine hundred and ninety nine billion, nine hundred and ninety nine million, nine hundred and ninety thousand, nine hundred and ninety nine. Fortunately, however, most people have mastered the system of Arabic numerals, in which each of the infinitely many natural numbers has a name, even though no one will ever use them all. In calling them 'names', I assume they are rigid designators the referents of which are fixed by descriptions that must be implicitly be mastered by those who understand them. Each of these distinct names can be taken as designating a distinct cardinality property, as long as we don t run out of multiples to bear those properties. This might seem to be a worry, since it seems likely that there are only finitely many electrons in the universe, and so only finitely many multiples of concrete things. But it s not a worry since we aren t restricted to counting only concrete things. We can also count multiples which have plural properties as constituents, including cardinality properties (numbers) we have already encountered. Since this ensures that there will be no end to larger and larger multiples, it also ensures the existence of infinitely many distinct cardinality properties. 6

7 As our former student Mario Gomez Torrente has recently pointed out, this picture gives us an opportunity to explain our knowledge of numbers. Consider the child inferring from her perceptual knowledge that the number of fingers I am holding up is 3. At first, she does this by counting -- saying the first three positive numerals -- pairing them off without remainder with the fingers I am holding up. In time, counting won t always be necessary, because she will be able to recognize at a glance when she is perceiving trios of familiar types. At this point the child has the concept, being a trio of things (of some common type or other), which is the plural property being three in number i.e. the number 3. The child learns a few other small numbers in the same way initially by counting, but eventually by ordinary perceptual recognition, and the formation of related perceptual beliefs. She will be able to perceptually recognize instances of these numbers, even though counting will remain the fallback method when in doubt, or when the multiples increase in size. Because of this, it is reasonable to think that much of our knowledge of natural numbers is knowledge of cardinality properties grounded initially in perception (visual and otherwise), in cognitive recognition of things being of various types, and in cognitive action e.g., counting the items falling under a given concept by reciting the relevant numerals while focusing one s attention on different individuals of a given type falling under the concept. When thinking of things in this way, it is important to realize that one doesn t first learn what numbers are, and then use them to count. On the contrary, one first learns the practice of articulating certain sequences sounds (i.e. sequences of numerals) and pairing them off with sequences of things. That is the origin of counting. The point at which one begins to recognize numbers and use numerals to refer to them is the point at which one has mastered this practice and integrated it into one s cognitive life. In saying things like, The number of blue books on the table is four, but the number of red ones is only three, one uses the 7

8 numerals to attribute cardinality properties of multiples. The properties one attributes are numbers, which exist independently of us and of our language, but which we come to cognize only in virtue of the linguistic, and other symbolic, routines we have mastered. Although that's the basic idea, various clarifications -- linguistic and otherwise -- are needed. First a bit of grammar. I am thinking of the English word 'three' on analogy with the word 'blue' as capable of performing three grammatical functions: First, these words can be used to designate certain properties of which other properties are predicated, as in and Blue is the color of a cloudless sky at noon and Three is the number of singers in the group. Second, they can combine with the copula to form predicates, as in The sky is blue and We are three, said by Peter, Paul, and Mary in answer to the question How many are you? Third, they can modify predicates, as in There is a blue shirt in the closet and There are three singers on stage. On the analysis I suggest, the numeral 'three' designates a plural property that applies to Peter, Paul, and Mary without applying to any one of them; the compound property being three singers on the stage applies to some individuals who are (collectively) three iff each is a singer on the stage. 2 In a formal language, these distinct uses of the word 'three' might be regimented into uniform uses of different words, but that needn't concern us here. The idea that properties, which we predicate of things in the domain of so-called individuals, are themselves members of that domain may open the door to paradox, unless restrictions of some sort are adopted. Though that is a matter of theoretical concern, that concern is not unique to this project which can, perhaps, be set aside for now. 2 To say that there are at least 3 singers on the stage is to say that some individuals who are three in number are each on the stage. To say that there are exactly 3 singers on the stage is to say that some individuals who are 3 in number are each singers on the stage, but no singers on the stage are collectively greater than 3. 8

9 What about the following observation, which updates a passage from section 46 of the Foundations of Arithmetic? While looking at Peter, Paul, and Mary standing on the stage next to Bill Halley and the Comets, I may say, equally, the number of singing groups on the stage is 2 or the number of singers on the stage is 10. Indeed, I can say both. I see 10 singers and I see 2 singing groups. In saying this, I am not saying that any of the things I see are both 2 and 10 in number. One might be driven to this if one thought that the 10 singers simply were the two groups. But they aren't. Although the 10 singers constituted the two singing groups there is no genuine identity in the offing. For example, the singers all had the property of being much older than the groups, though neither of the singing groups had the property of being much older than the groups. To count items, the items must already be cognitively individuated. The number 3 is the plural property applying to all and only those individuals x, y, and z none of which is identical with any other. In saying this, we presuppose the individuation we need in stipulating that the values of the variables are different. Nothing more is needed to predicate the plural property. Given this, we can accommodate what Frege was getting at in section 46. So far I have talked only about the very early stages of our knowledge of natural numbers. I claim some of this knowledge is perceptual belief that qualifies as knowledge. If one's knowledge of each of two things, x and y, that it is a finger is perceptual in this sense, and one's knowledge that x isn't y is also perceptual, then one's knowledge that x and y are two in number is also perceptual. If the fingers had been painted blue one could truly say, not only that one sees that those fingers are blue, but also that one sees that they are two in number. Indeed, if two people are standing at a distance from someone holding up two blue fingers, one of the observers, who is having trouble making out precisely what is being displayed, might ask Do you see the color of the fingers he is holding up? or Do you 9

10 see the number of fingers he is holding up? The one with better vision might reply, Yes, I see the color of those fingers; they are blue or Yes, I see the number of those fingers; they are two. So, it seems, there is a more or less ordinary sense of 'see' in which we can truly say that some color properties and some natural numbers, i.e. plural cardinality properties, can be seen. Don't wring your hands over the fact that this is surprising. If philosophy is worth doing, it should sometimes provide surprising, even shocking, knowledge. Here, it is knowledge about some of our knowledge of numbers. Systematic knowledge of arithmetic e.g. of the axioms and logical consequences of Peano Arithmetic is, of course, more complicated. This knowledge can t all be logical knowledge of the sort Frege imagined. If natural numbers are cardinality properties, logic alone can t guarantee that there are any individuals, multiples, or distinct cardinality properties of multiples, let alone infinitely many. But we can use logic plus updated versions of Frege s definitions of successor and natural number -- involving plural properties of multiples rather than sets to derive systematic knowledge of natural numbers. The definition of successor tells us that the plural property N is the successor of the plural property M if and only if there is some property F of individuals such that, some things that are F, of which a given object o is one, are N in number, while the Fs, excluding o, are M in number. Given definitions of zero and successor we can define natural numbers in the normal way as plural properties of which every property true of zero and of the successor of anything it is true of, is true. 3 From this plus our initial perceptually-based knowledge, we can derive arithmetical truths. We can come to know that zero isn't the successor of anything by observing that if it were, then some property true of nothing would have to be true of something. We can come 3 See pp of Boolos (1984) for a fuller discussion. 10

11 to know that no natural number M has two successors by observing that otherwise there would have to be properties N1 and N2 such that the N1s can't be exhaustively paired off with the N2s without remainder, even though there are objects o N1 and o N2 such that the N1s excluding o N1 and the N2s excluding o N2 are both M in number -- and so can be paired off. The impossibility of this is easy to see. Knowledge of the companion axiom, that different natural numbers N1 and N2 can't have the same successor, is explained in the same way. As for the axiom that every natural number has a successor, this can be seen to be true when we realize that the plural properties we arrive at by counting can themselves be included in later multiples we count. This ensures that we can always add one of them to any multiple that has given us a plural property M we have already reached. In this way, plural cardinality properties can allow us to explain not only the earliest knowledge of natural numbers we acquired as children, but also how systematic knowledge of elementary number theory can be acquired. There are, of course, other ways of expanding the meager knowledge of arithmetic acquired in kindergarten, or earlier. Most of us learned our arithmetic -- addition, subtraction, multiplication, division, and exponentiation -- in the early grades, without being exposed to the Peano axioms. No matter. The efficient, user-friendly computational routines we mastered are compatible with the epistemological and metaphysical perspective advocated here. That said, I don't claim to know that this perspective is correct. However, I take it to be more promising than any set-theoretic account of natural numbers. Paul Benacerraf's original problem alerted us the fact that any such reduction purporting to tell us what natural numbers really are -- as opposed to what, for one or another purpose, we might find it convenient to take them to be -- should provide a principled reason for selecting one and 11

12 only one set theoretic-reduction from among the many non-equivalent ways of identifying natural numbers with sets. Although each identifies individual numbers with sets that differ from those provided by other reductions, the different reductive systems do an equally good job of preserving all arithmetical truths, and the relationships among them. So, if this were the only criterion for justifying a reduction, we would have no reason for thinking that any of those reductions is uniquely correct. We might even have reason for doubting that any is correct. Surely, one may think, if the number three is identical with some set, there should be a reason it is one in particular, rather than any others. But, Benacerraf plausibly suggests, no set-theoretic reduction provides such a reason. If one believes, as I do, that there really are natural numbers, which all of us who have learned grade-school arithmetic know some things about, and which number theorists know much more about, then we should be looking for a metaphysical account that best facilitates an explanation of this knowledge. Although some set-theoretic accounts might be more promising than others, I think Paul was right in suggesting that set theoretical reductions can't pass the test. It's not that we don't have knowledge of sets; surely we must. But I doubt that it comes directly from anything as immediate as counting or perception. Rather, I suspect it arises from different sorts of collective activities, particularly those in which teams, committees, and groups of coordinated individuals collectively succeed in doing certain things than no one of the individuals does -- like winning a football game, pushing a stalled car to the side of the road, or carrying an object too heavy for any one of them. After we have admitted these, I suspect we find occasions to recognize collections of things that are noticeably similar in some way, even though they may not collectively do anything. Later, it occurs to us that we have no reason to exclude arbitrary collections of things. At this point the axioms of set theory can be considered and accepted. 12

13 Even then, however, it is hard to take seriously the idea that natural numbers are sets -- partly for the reasons that Paul stressed in the 1960s and 1970s, but also because by the time children and young adults have reached the required level to appreciate set-theoretic abstraction, the natural numbers have already been firmly cemented in their minds through a conceptual process in which the numbers are naturally taken to be plural properties. It is tempting to put it this way: just as the color blue is naturally understood to be the property commonly possessed by this, that, and the other individual blue thing, so the number three is naturally understood as the property commonly possessed by this, that, and the other multiple, each of which is three in number. But, this way of expressing the idea can be misleading. It makes it sound as if multiples were a kind of thing, which could, in principle, be counted, like anything else. That can't be. When we say that Peter, Paul, and Mary are three, nothing of any kind is said to be three. On the story I am telling, being three in number is a property that is never correctly predicated of anything of any type. Rather it is a property that is predicated of some things -- e.g. Peter, Paul, and Mary -- without being predicated either of them individually, or of any other single thing. The idea is coherent and, I think, intriguing. But it is one that was made explicit relatively recently and, for that reason perhaps, seems not yet to have penetrated very far into philosophical theorizing. This makes me uneasy. Can it really be as psychologically elementary as I have been making out, while being as philosophically unfamiliar as it seems to be? I'm not sure, which is the main reason I chose to talk about it here today. I can think of no better place than Princeton, and no more insightful and reliable experts than my former colleagues John, Gideon, and Paul -- among others here -- to help me think about it. 13

Understanding Truth Scott Soames Précis Philosophy and Phenomenological Research Volume LXV, No. 2, 2002

Understanding Truth Scott Soames Précis Philosophy and Phenomenological Research Volume LXV, No. 2, 2002 1 Symposium on Understanding Truth By Scott Soames Précis Philosophy and Phenomenological Research Volume LXV, No. 2, 2002 2 Precis of Understanding Truth Scott Soames Understanding Truth aims to illuminate

More information

What is the Frege/Russell Analysis of Quantification? Scott Soames

What is the Frege/Russell Analysis of Quantification? Scott Soames What is the Frege/Russell Analysis of Quantification? Scott Soames The Frege-Russell analysis of quantification was a fundamental advance in semantics and philosophical logic. Abstracting away from details

More information

Boghossian & Harman on the analytic theory of the a priori

Boghossian & Harman on the analytic theory of the a priori Boghossian & Harman on the analytic theory of the a priori PHIL 83104 November 2, 2011 Both Boghossian and Harman address themselves to the question of whether our a priori knowledge can be explained in

More information

Coordination Problems

Coordination Problems Philosophy and Phenomenological Research Philosophy and Phenomenological Research Vol. LXXXI No. 2, September 2010 Ó 2010 Philosophy and Phenomenological Research, LLC Coordination Problems scott soames

More information

Propositions as Cognitive Acts Scott Soames Draft March 1, My theory of propositions starts from two premises: (i) agents represent things as

Propositions as Cognitive Acts Scott Soames Draft March 1, My theory of propositions starts from two premises: (i) agents represent things as Propositions as Cognitive Acts Scott Soames Draft March 1, 2014 My theory of propositions starts from two premises: (i) agents represent things as being certain ways when they perceive, visualize, imagine,

More information

THE SEMANTIC REALISM OF STROUD S RESPONSE TO AUSTIN S ARGUMENT AGAINST SCEPTICISM

THE SEMANTIC REALISM OF STROUD S RESPONSE TO AUSTIN S ARGUMENT AGAINST SCEPTICISM SKÉPSIS, ISSN 1981-4194, ANO VII, Nº 14, 2016, p. 33-39. THE SEMANTIC REALISM OF STROUD S RESPONSE TO AUSTIN S ARGUMENT AGAINST SCEPTICISM ALEXANDRE N. MACHADO Universidade Federal do Paraná (UFPR) Email:

More information

Now consider a verb - like is pretty. Does this also stand for something?

Now consider a verb - like is pretty. Does this also stand for something? Kripkenstein The rule-following paradox is a paradox about how it is possible for us to mean anything by the words of our language. More precisely, it is an argument which seems to show that it is impossible

More information

Skepticism and Internalism

Skepticism and Internalism Skepticism and Internalism John Greco Abstract: This paper explores a familiar skeptical problematic and considers some strategies for responding to it. Section 1 reconstructs and disambiguates the skeptical

More information

On Infinite Size. Bruno Whittle

On Infinite Size. Bruno Whittle To appear in Oxford Studies in Metaphysics On Infinite Size Bruno Whittle Late in the 19th century, Cantor introduced the notion of the power, or the cardinality, of an infinite set. 1 According to Cantor

More information

Philosophy 5340 Epistemology. Topic 6: Theories of Justification: Foundationalism versus Coherentism. Part 2: Susan Haack s Foundherentist Approach

Philosophy 5340 Epistemology. Topic 6: Theories of Justification: Foundationalism versus Coherentism. Part 2: Susan Haack s Foundherentist Approach Philosophy 5340 Epistemology Topic 6: Theories of Justification: Foundationalism versus Coherentism Part 2: Susan Haack s Foundherentist Approach Susan Haack, "A Foundherentist Theory of Empirical Justification"

More information

part one MACROSTRUCTURE Cambridge University Press X - A Theory of Argument Mark Vorobej Excerpt More information

part one MACROSTRUCTURE Cambridge University Press X - A Theory of Argument Mark Vorobej Excerpt More information part one MACROSTRUCTURE 1 Arguments 1.1 Authors and Audiences An argument is a social activity, the goal of which is interpersonal rational persuasion. More precisely, we ll say that an argument occurs

More information

PROSPECTIVE TEACHERS UNDERSTANDING OF PROOF: WHAT IF THE TRUTH SET OF AN OPEN SENTENCE IS BROADER THAN THAT COVERED BY THE PROOF?

PROSPECTIVE TEACHERS UNDERSTANDING OF PROOF: WHAT IF THE TRUTH SET OF AN OPEN SENTENCE IS BROADER THAN THAT COVERED BY THE PROOF? PROSPECTIVE TEACHERS UNDERSTANDING OF PROOF: WHAT IF THE TRUTH SET OF AN OPEN SENTENCE IS BROADER THAN THAT COVERED BY THE PROOF? Andreas J. Stylianides*, Gabriel J. Stylianides*, & George N. Philippou**

More information

Varieties of Apriority

Varieties of Apriority S E V E N T H E X C U R S U S Varieties of Apriority T he notions of a priori knowledge and justification play a central role in this work. There are many ways in which one can understand the a priori,

More information

Ayer on the criterion of verifiability

Ayer on the criterion of verifiability Ayer on the criterion of verifiability November 19, 2004 1 The critique of metaphysics............................. 1 2 Observation statements............................... 2 3 In principle verifiability...............................

More information

Language, Meaning, and Information: A Case Study on the Path from Philosophy to Science Scott Soames

Language, Meaning, and Information: A Case Study on the Path from Philosophy to Science Scott Soames Language, Meaning, and Information: A Case Study on the Path from Philosophy to Science Scott Soames Near the beginning of the final lecture of The Philosophy of Logical Atomism, in 1918, Bertrand Russell

More information

Wright on response-dependence and self-knowledge

Wright on response-dependence and self-knowledge Wright on response-dependence and self-knowledge March 23, 2004 1 Response-dependent and response-independent concepts........... 1 1.1 The intuitive distinction......................... 1 1.2 Basic equations

More information

PHL340 Handout 8: Evaluating Dogmatism

PHL340 Handout 8: Evaluating Dogmatism PHL340 Handout 8: Evaluating Dogmatism 1 Dogmatism Last class we looked at Jim Pryor s paper on dogmatism about perceptual justification (for background on the notion of justification, see the handout

More information

Propositions as Cognitive Event Types

Propositions as Cognitive Event Types Propositions as Cognitive Event Types By Scott Soames USC School of Philosophy Chapter 6 New Thinking about Propositions By Jeff King, Scott Soames, Jeff Speaks Oxford University Press 1 Propositions as

More information

From Transcendental Logic to Transcendental Deduction

From Transcendental Logic to Transcendental Deduction From Transcendental Logic to Transcendental Deduction Let me see if I can say a few things to re-cap our first discussion of the Transcendental Logic, and help you get a foothold for what follows. Kant

More information

Comments on Saul Kripke s Philosophical Troubles

Comments on Saul Kripke s Philosophical Troubles Comments on Saul Kripke s Philosophical Troubles Theodore Sider Disputatio 5 (2015): 67 80 1. Introduction My comments will focus on some loosely connected issues from The First Person and Frege s Theory

More information

In Defense of Radical Empiricism. Joseph Benjamin Riegel. Chapel Hill 2006

In Defense of Radical Empiricism. Joseph Benjamin Riegel. Chapel Hill 2006 In Defense of Radical Empiricism Joseph Benjamin Riegel A thesis submitted to the faculty of the University of North Carolina at Chapel Hill in partial fulfillment of the requirements for the degree of

More information

Jerry A. Fodor. Hume Variations John Biro Volume 31, Number 1, (2005) 173-176. Your use of the HUME STUDIES archive indicates your acceptance of HUME STUDIES Terms and Conditions of Use, available at http://www.humesociety.org/hs/about/terms.html.

More information

Ayer s linguistic theory of the a priori

Ayer s linguistic theory of the a priori Ayer s linguistic theory of the a priori phil 43904 Jeff Speaks December 4, 2007 1 The problem of a priori knowledge....................... 1 2 Necessity and the a priori............................ 2

More information

Bertrand Russell Proper Names, Adjectives and Verbs 1

Bertrand Russell Proper Names, Adjectives and Verbs 1 Bertrand Russell Proper Names, Adjectives and Verbs 1 Analysis 46 Philosophical grammar can shed light on philosophical questions. Grammatical differences can be used as a source of discovery and a guide

More information

How Not to Defend Metaphysical Realism (Southwestern Philosophical Review, Vol , 19-27)

How Not to Defend Metaphysical Realism (Southwestern Philosophical Review, Vol , 19-27) How Not to Defend Metaphysical Realism (Southwestern Philosophical Review, Vol 3 1986, 19-27) John Collier Department of Philosophy Rice University November 21, 1986 Putnam's writings on realism(1) have

More information

Is mental content prior to linguistic meaning?

Is mental content prior to linguistic meaning? Is mental content prior to linguistic meaning? Jeff Speaks September 23, 2004 1 The problem of intentionality....................... 3 2 Belief states and mental representations................. 5 2.1

More information

Verificationism. PHIL September 27, 2011

Verificationism. PHIL September 27, 2011 Verificationism PHIL 83104 September 27, 2011 1. The critique of metaphysics... 1 2. Observation statements... 2 3. In principle verifiability... 3 4. Strong verifiability... 3 4.1. Conclusive verifiability

More information

The Question of Metaphysics

The Question of Metaphysics The Question of Metaphysics metaphysics seriously. Second, I want to argue that the currently popular hands-off conception of metaphysical theorising is unable to provide a satisfactory answer to the question

More information

Russell s Problems of Philosophy

Russell s Problems of Philosophy Russell s Problems of Philosophy UNIVERSALS & OUR KNOWLEDGE OF THEM F e b r u a r y 2 Today : 1. Review A Priori Knowledge 2. The Case for Universals 3. Universals to the Rescue! 4. On Philosophy Essays

More information

Kripke s skeptical paradox

Kripke s skeptical paradox Kripke s skeptical paradox phil 93914 Jeff Speaks March 13, 2008 1 The paradox.................................... 1 2 Proposed solutions to the paradox....................... 3 2.1 Meaning as determined

More information

Comments on Ontological Anti-Realism

Comments on Ontological Anti-Realism Comments on Ontological Anti-Realism Cian Dorr INPC 2007 In 1950, Quine inaugurated a strange new way of talking about philosophy. The hallmark of this approach is a propensity to take ordinary colloquial

More information

the aim is to specify the structure of the world in the form of certain basic truths from which all truths can be derived. (xviii)

the aim is to specify the structure of the world in the form of certain basic truths from which all truths can be derived. (xviii) PHIL 5983: Naturalness and Fundamentality Seminar Prof. Funkhouser Spring 2017 Week 8: Chalmers, Constructing the World Notes (Introduction, Chapters 1-2) Introduction * We are introduced to the ideas

More information

BEGINNINGLESS PAST AND ENDLESS FUTURE: REPLY TO CRAIG. Wes Morriston. In a recent paper, I claimed that if a familiar line of argument against

BEGINNINGLESS PAST AND ENDLESS FUTURE: REPLY TO CRAIG. Wes Morriston. In a recent paper, I claimed that if a familiar line of argument against Forthcoming in Faith and Philosophy BEGINNINGLESS PAST AND ENDLESS FUTURE: REPLY TO CRAIG Wes Morriston In a recent paper, I claimed that if a familiar line of argument against the possibility of a beginningless

More information

Class #14: October 13 Gödel s Platonism

Class #14: October 13 Gödel s Platonism Philosophy 405: Knowledge, Truth and Mathematics Fall 2010 Hamilton College Russell Marcus Class #14: October 13 Gödel s Platonism I. The Continuum Hypothesis and Its Independence The continuum problem

More information

Theories of propositions

Theories of propositions Theories of propositions phil 93515 Jeff Speaks January 16, 2007 1 Commitment to propositions.......................... 1 2 A Fregean theory of reference.......................... 2 3 Three theories of

More information

15. Russell on definite descriptions

15. Russell on definite descriptions 15. Russell on definite descriptions Martín Abreu Zavaleta July 30, 2015 Russell was another top logician and philosopher of his time. Like Frege, Russell got interested in denotational expressions as

More information

Propositions as Cambridge properties

Propositions as Cambridge properties Propositions as Cambridge properties Jeff Speaks July 25, 2018 1 Propositions as Cambridge properties................... 1 2 How well do properties fit the theoretical role of propositions?..... 4 2.1

More information

Is there a good epistemological argument against platonism? DAVID LIGGINS

Is there a good epistemological argument against platonism? DAVID LIGGINS [This is the penultimate draft of an article that appeared in Analysis 66.2 (April 2006), 135-41, available here by permission of Analysis, the Analysis Trust, and Blackwell Publishing. The definitive

More information

Has Nagel uncovered a form of idealism?

Has Nagel uncovered a form of idealism? Has Nagel uncovered a form of idealism? Author: Terence Rajivan Edward, University of Manchester. Abstract. In the sixth chapter of The View from Nowhere, Thomas Nagel attempts to identify a form of idealism.

More information

Lecture 3. I argued in the previous lecture for a relationist solution to Frege's puzzle, one which

Lecture 3. I argued in the previous lecture for a relationist solution to Frege's puzzle, one which 1 Lecture 3 I argued in the previous lecture for a relationist solution to Frege's puzzle, one which posits a semantic difference between the pairs of names 'Cicero', 'Cicero' and 'Cicero', 'Tully' even

More information

Conference on the Epistemology of Keith Lehrer, PUCRS, Porto Alegre (Brazil), June

Conference on the Epistemology of Keith Lehrer, PUCRS, Porto Alegre (Brazil), June 2 Reply to Comesaña* Réplica a Comesaña Carl Ginet** 1. In the Sentence-Relativity section of his comments, Comesaña discusses my attempt (in the Relativity to Sentences section of my paper) to convince

More information

Cognitive Significance, Attitude Ascriptions, and Ways of Believing Propositions. David Braun. University of Rochester

Cognitive Significance, Attitude Ascriptions, and Ways of Believing Propositions. David Braun. University of Rochester Cognitive Significance, Attitude Ascriptions, and Ways of Believing Propositions by David Braun University of Rochester Presented at the Pacific APA in San Francisco on March 31, 2001 1. Naive Russellianism

More information

KANT, MORAL DUTY AND THE DEMANDS OF PURE PRACTICAL REASON. The law is reason unaffected by desire.

KANT, MORAL DUTY AND THE DEMANDS OF PURE PRACTICAL REASON. The law is reason unaffected by desire. KANT, MORAL DUTY AND THE DEMANDS OF PURE PRACTICAL REASON The law is reason unaffected by desire. Aristotle, Politics Book III (1287a32) THE BIG IDEAS TO MASTER Kantian formalism Kantian constructivism

More information

ALTERNATIVE SELF-DEFEAT ARGUMENTS: A REPLY TO MIZRAHI

ALTERNATIVE SELF-DEFEAT ARGUMENTS: A REPLY TO MIZRAHI ALTERNATIVE SELF-DEFEAT ARGUMENTS: A REPLY TO MIZRAHI Michael HUEMER ABSTRACT: I address Moti Mizrahi s objections to my use of the Self-Defeat Argument for Phenomenal Conservatism (PC). Mizrahi contends

More information

Russell: On Denoting

Russell: On Denoting Russell: On Denoting DENOTING PHRASES Russell includes all kinds of quantified subject phrases ( a man, every man, some man etc.) but his main interest is in definite descriptions: the present King of

More information

Ludwig Wittgenstein: Philosophical Investigations

Ludwig Wittgenstein: Philosophical Investigations Ludwig Wittgenstein: Philosophical Investigations Published posthumously in 1953 Style and method Style o A collection of 693 numbered remarks (from one sentence up to one page, usually one paragraph long).

More information

Ryle on Systematically Misleading Expresssions

Ryle on Systematically Misleading Expresssions Ryle on Systematically Misleading Expresssions G. J. Mattey Fall, 2005 / Philosophy 156 Ordinary-Language Philosophy Wittgenstein s emphasis on the way language is used in ordinary situations heralded

More information

Philosophical Issues, vol. 8 (1997), pp

Philosophical Issues, vol. 8 (1997), pp Philosophical Issues, vol. 8 (1997), pp. 313-323. Different Kinds of Kind Terms: A Reply to Sosa and Kim 1 by Geoffrey Sayre-McCord University of North Carolina at Chapel Hill In "'Good' on Twin Earth"

More information

Review Article Blueprint for a Science of Mind:

Review Article Blueprint for a Science of Mind: Mind & Language ISSN 0268-1064 Vol. 9 No. 4 December 1994 @ Basil Blackwell Ltd. 1994, 108 Cowley Road, Oxford OX4 IJF, UK and 238 Main Street, Cambridge, M A 02142, USA. Review Article Blueprint for a

More information

The Kripkenstein Paradox and the Private World. In his paper, Wittgenstein on Rules and Private Languages, Kripke expands upon a conclusion

The Kripkenstein Paradox and the Private World. In his paper, Wittgenstein on Rules and Private Languages, Kripke expands upon a conclusion 24.251: Philosophy of Language Paper 2: S.A. Kripke, On Rules and Private Language 21 December 2011 The Kripkenstein Paradox and the Private World In his paper, Wittgenstein on Rules and Private Languages,

More information

From Necessary Truth to Necessary Existence

From Necessary Truth to Necessary Existence Prequel for Section 4.2 of Defending the Correspondence Theory Published by PJP VII, 1 From Necessary Truth to Necessary Existence Abstract I introduce new details in an argument for necessarily existing

More information

Early Russell on Philosophical Grammar

Early Russell on Philosophical Grammar Early Russell on Philosophical Grammar G. J. Mattey Fall, 2005 / Philosophy 156 Philosophical Grammar The study of grammar, in my opinion, is capable of throwing far more light on philosophical questions

More information

Draft January 19, 2010 Draft January 19, True at. Scott Soames School of Philosophy USC. To Appear In a Symposium on

Draft January 19, 2010 Draft January 19, True at. Scott Soames School of Philosophy USC. To Appear In a Symposium on Draft January 19, 2010 Draft January 19, 2010 True at By Scott Soames School of Philosophy USC To Appear In a Symposium on Herman Cappelen and John Hawthorne Relativism and Monadic Truth In Analysis Reviews

More information

Notes on Bertrand Russell s The Problems of Philosophy (Hackett 1990 reprint of the 1912 Oxford edition, Chapters XII, XIII, XIV, )

Notes on Bertrand Russell s The Problems of Philosophy (Hackett 1990 reprint of the 1912 Oxford edition, Chapters XII, XIII, XIV, ) Notes on Bertrand Russell s The Problems of Philosophy (Hackett 1990 reprint of the 1912 Oxford edition, Chapters XII, XIII, XIV, 119-152) Chapter XII Truth and Falsehood [pp. 119-130] Russell begins here

More information

Understanding, Modality, Logical Operators. Christopher Peacocke. Columbia University

Understanding, Modality, Logical Operators. Christopher Peacocke. Columbia University Understanding, Modality, Logical Operators Christopher Peacocke Columbia University Timothy Williamson s The Philosophy of Philosophy stimulates on every page. I would like to discuss every chapter. To

More information

The Language Revolution Russell Marcus Fall 2014

The Language Revolution Russell Marcus Fall 2014 The Language Revolution Russell Marcus Fall 2014 Class #3 Meinong and Mill The Last of the Pre-Revolutionaries Marcus, The Language Revolution, Fall 2014, Slide 1 Truth, Language, and Ideas The Moderns

More information

Revelation, Humility, and the Structure of the World. David J. Chalmers

Revelation, Humility, and the Structure of the World. David J. Chalmers Revelation, Humility, and the Structure of the World David J. Chalmers Revelation and Humility Revelation holds for a property P iff Possessing the concept of P enables us to know what property P is Humility

More information

UC Berkeley, Philosophy 142, Spring 2016

UC Berkeley, Philosophy 142, Spring 2016 Logical Consequence UC Berkeley, Philosophy 142, Spring 2016 John MacFarlane 1 Intuitive characterizations of consequence Modal: It is necessary (or apriori) that, if the premises are true, the conclusion

More information

Wittgenstein and Moore s Paradox

Wittgenstein and Moore s Paradox Wittgenstein and Moore s Paradox Marie McGinn, Norwich Introduction In Part II, Section x, of the Philosophical Investigations (PI ), Wittgenstein discusses what is known as Moore s Paradox. Wittgenstein

More information

The Indeterminacy of Translation: Fifty Years Later

The Indeterminacy of Translation: Fifty Years Later The Indeterminacy of Translation: Fifty Years Later Tufts University BIBLID [0873-626X (2012) 32; pp. 385-393] Abstract The paper considers the Quinean heritage of the argument for the indeterminacy of

More information

How Do We Know Anything about Mathematics? - A Defence of Platonism

How Do We Know Anything about Mathematics? - A Defence of Platonism How Do We Know Anything about Mathematics? - A Defence of Platonism Majda Trobok University of Rijeka original scientific paper UDK: 141.131 1:51 510.21 ABSTRACT In this paper I will try to say something

More information

Physicalism and Conceptual Analysis * Esa Díaz-León.

Physicalism and Conceptual Analysis * Esa Díaz-León. Physicalism and Conceptual Analysis * Esa Díaz-León pip01ed@sheffield.ac.uk Physicalism is a widely held claim about the nature of the world. But, as it happens, it also has its detractors. The first step

More information

4181 ( 10.5), = 625 ( 11.2), = 125 ( 13). 311 PPO, p Cf. also: All the errors that have been made in this chapter of the

4181 ( 10.5), = 625 ( 11.2), = 125 ( 13). 311 PPO, p Cf. also: All the errors that have been made in this chapter of the 122 Wittgenstein s later writings 14. Mathematics We have seen in previous chapters that mathematical statements are paradigmatic cases of internal relations. 310 And indeed, the core in Wittgenstein s

More information

DISCUSSION THE GUISE OF A REASON

DISCUSSION THE GUISE OF A REASON NADEEM J.Z. HUSSAIN DISCUSSION THE GUISE OF A REASON The articles collected in David Velleman s The Possibility of Practical Reason are a snapshot or rather a film-strip of part of a philosophical endeavour

More information

Review of Constructive Empiricism: Epistemology and the Philosophy of Science

Review of Constructive Empiricism: Epistemology and the Philosophy of Science Review of Constructive Empiricism: Epistemology and the Philosophy of Science Constructive Empiricism (CE) quickly became famous for its immunity from the most devastating criticisms that brought down

More information

Qualitative and quantitative inference to the best theory. reply to iikka Niiniluoto Kuipers, Theodorus

Qualitative and quantitative inference to the best theory. reply to iikka Niiniluoto Kuipers, Theodorus University of Groningen Qualitative and quantitative inference to the best theory. reply to iikka Niiniluoto Kuipers, Theodorus Published in: EPRINTS-BOOK-TITLE IMPORTANT NOTE: You are advised to consult

More information

15 Does God have a Nature?

15 Does God have a Nature? 15 Does God have a Nature? 15.1 Plantinga s Question So far I have argued for a theory of creation and the use of mathematical ways of thinking that help us to locate God. The question becomes how can

More information

Chalmers on Epistemic Content. Alex Byrne, MIT

Chalmers on Epistemic Content. Alex Byrne, MIT Veracruz SOFIA conference, 12/01 Chalmers on Epistemic Content Alex Byrne, MIT 1. Let us say that a thought is about an object o just in case the truth value of the thought at any possible world W depends

More information

Introduction. I. Proof of the Minor Premise ( All reality is completely intelligible )

Introduction. I. Proof of the Minor Premise ( All reality is completely intelligible ) Philosophical Proof of God: Derived from Principles in Bernard Lonergan s Insight May 2014 Robert J. Spitzer, S.J., Ph.D. Magis Center of Reason and Faith Lonergan s proof may be stated as follows: Introduction

More information

(1) A phrase may be denoting, and yet not denote anything; e.g., 'the present King of France'.

(1) A phrase may be denoting, and yet not denote anything; e.g., 'the present King of France'. On Denoting By Russell Based on the 1903 article By a 'denoting phrase' I mean a phrase such as any one of the following: a man, some man, any man, every man, all men, the present King of England, the

More information

1 What is conceptual analysis and what is the problem?

1 What is conceptual analysis and what is the problem? 1 What is conceptual analysis and what is the problem? 1.1 What is conceptual analysis? In this book, I am going to defend the viability of conceptual analysis as a philosophical method. It therefore seems

More information

Full-Blooded Platonism 1. (Forthcoming in An Historical Introduction to the Philosophy of Mathematics, Bloomsbury Press)

Full-Blooded Platonism 1. (Forthcoming in An Historical Introduction to the Philosophy of Mathematics, Bloomsbury Press) Mark Balaguer Department of Philosophy California State University, Los Angeles Full-Blooded Platonism 1 (Forthcoming in An Historical Introduction to the Philosophy of Mathematics, Bloomsbury Press) In

More information

Propositions as Cognitive Acts Scott Soames. sentence, or the content of a representational mental state, involves knowing which

Propositions as Cognitive Acts Scott Soames. sentence, or the content of a representational mental state, involves knowing which Propositions as Cognitive Acts Scott Soames My topic is the concept of information needed in the study of language and mind. It is widely acknowledged that knowing the meaning of an ordinary declarative

More information

[3.] Bertrand Russell. 1

[3.] Bertrand Russell. 1 [3.] Bertrand Russell. 1 [3.1.] Biographical Background. 1872: born in the city of Trellech, in the county of Monmouthshire, now part of Wales 2 One of his grandfathers was Lord John Russell, who twice

More information

Each copy of any part of a JSTOR transmission must contain the same copyright notice that appears on the screen or printed page of such transmission.

Each copy of any part of a JSTOR transmission must contain the same copyright notice that appears on the screen or printed page of such transmission. The Physical World Author(s): Barry Stroud Source: Proceedings of the Aristotelian Society, New Series, Vol. 87 (1986-1987), pp. 263-277 Published by: Blackwell Publishing on behalf of The Aristotelian

More information

A solution to the problem of hijacked experience

A solution to the problem of hijacked experience A solution to the problem of hijacked experience Jill is not sure what Jack s current mood is, but she fears that he is angry with her. Then Jack steps into the room. Jill gets a good look at his face.

More information

Is Truth the Primary Epistemic Goal? Joseph Barnes

Is Truth the Primary Epistemic Goal? Joseph Barnes Is Truth the Primary Epistemic Goal? Joseph Barnes I. Motivation: what hangs on this question? II. How Primary? III. Kvanvig's argument that truth isn't the primary epistemic goal IV. David's argument

More information

RATIONALITY AND THEISTIC BELIEF, by Mark S. McLeod. Ithaca: Cornell University Press, Pp. xiv and 260. $37.50 (cloth).

RATIONALITY AND THEISTIC BELIEF, by Mark S. McLeod. Ithaca: Cornell University Press, Pp. xiv and 260. $37.50 (cloth). RATIONALITY AND THEISTIC BELIEF, by Mark S. McLeod. Ithaca: Cornell University Press, 1993. Pp. xiv and 260. $37.50 (cloth). For Faith and Philosophy, 1996 DANIEL HOWARD-SNYDER, Seattle Pacific University

More information

Right-Making, Reference, and Reduction

Right-Making, Reference, and Reduction Right-Making, Reference, and Reduction Kent State University BIBLID [0873-626X (2014) 39; pp. 139-145] Abstract The causal theory of reference (CTR) provides a well-articulated and widely-accepted account

More information

Stout s teleological theory of action

Stout s teleological theory of action Stout s teleological theory of action Jeff Speaks November 26, 2004 1 The possibility of externalist explanations of action................ 2 1.1 The distinction between externalist and internalist explanations

More information

Topics and Posterior Analytics. Philosophy 21 Fall, 2004 G. J. Mattey

Topics and Posterior Analytics. Philosophy 21 Fall, 2004 G. J. Mattey Topics and Posterior Analytics Philosophy 21 Fall, 2004 G. J. Mattey Logic Aristotle is the first philosopher to study systematically what we call logic Specifically, Aristotle investigated what we now

More information

Remarks on the philosophy of mathematics (1969) Paul Bernays

Remarks on the philosophy of mathematics (1969) Paul Bernays Bernays Project: Text No. 26 Remarks on the philosophy of mathematics (1969) Paul Bernays (Bemerkungen zur Philosophie der Mathematik) Translation by: Dirk Schlimm Comments: With corrections by Charles

More information

Class #3 - Meinong and Mill

Class #3 - Meinong and Mill Philosophy 308: The Language Revolution Fall 2014 Hamilton College Russell Marcus Class #3 - Meinong and Mill 1. Meinongian Subsistence The work of the Moderns on language shows us a problem arising in

More information

Warrant and accidentally true belief

Warrant and accidentally true belief Warrant and accidentally true belief ALVIN PLANTINGA My gratitude to Richard Greene and Nancy Balmert for their perceptive discussion of my account of warrant ('Two notions of warrant and Plantinga's solution

More information

Testimony and Moral Understanding Anthony T. Flood, Ph.D. Introduction

Testimony and Moral Understanding Anthony T. Flood, Ph.D. Introduction 24 Testimony and Moral Understanding Anthony T. Flood, Ph.D. Abstract: In this paper, I address Linda Zagzebski s analysis of the relation between moral testimony and understanding arguing that Aquinas

More information

Analytic Philosophy IUC Dubrovnik,

Analytic Philosophy IUC Dubrovnik, Analytic Philosophy IUC Dubrovnik, 10.5.-14.5.2010. Debating neo-logicism Majda Trobok University of Rijeka trobok@ffri.hr In this talk I will not address our official topic. Instead I will discuss some

More information

Analyticity and reference determiners

Analyticity and reference determiners Analyticity and reference determiners Jeff Speaks November 9, 2011 1. The language myth... 1 2. The definition of analyticity... 3 3. Defining containment... 4 4. Some remaining questions... 6 4.1. Reference

More information

Review of "The Tarskian Turn: Deflationism and Axiomatic Truth"

Review of The Tarskian Turn: Deflationism and Axiomatic Truth Essays in Philosophy Volume 13 Issue 2 Aesthetics and the Senses Article 19 August 2012 Review of "The Tarskian Turn: Deflationism and Axiomatic Truth" Matthew McKeon Michigan State University Follow this

More information

Ayer and Quine on the a priori

Ayer and Quine on the a priori Ayer and Quine on the a priori November 23, 2004 1 The problem of a priori knowledge Ayer s book is a defense of a thoroughgoing empiricism, not only about what is required for a belief to be justified

More information

MARK KAPLAN AND LAWRENCE SKLAR. Received 2 February, 1976) Surely an aim of science is the discovery of the truth. Truth may not be the

MARK KAPLAN AND LAWRENCE SKLAR. Received 2 February, 1976) Surely an aim of science is the discovery of the truth. Truth may not be the MARK KAPLAN AND LAWRENCE SKLAR RATIONALITY AND TRUTH Received 2 February, 1976) Surely an aim of science is the discovery of the truth. Truth may not be the sole aim, as Popper and others have so clearly

More information

Counterparts and Compositional Nihilism: A Reply to A. J. Cotnoir

Counterparts and Compositional Nihilism: A Reply to A. J. Cotnoir Thought ISSN 2161-2234 ORIGINAL ARTICLE Counterparts and Compositional Nihilism: University of Kentucky DOI:10.1002/tht3.92 1 A brief summary of Cotnoir s view One of the primary burdens of the mereological

More information

Our Knowledge of Mathematical Objects

Our Knowledge of Mathematical Objects 1 Our Knowledge of Mathematical Objects I have recently been attempting to provide a new approach to the philosophy of mathematics, which I call procedural postulationism. It shares with the traditional

More information

The Paradox of the stone and two concepts of omnipotence

The Paradox of the stone and two concepts of omnipotence Filo Sofija Nr 30 (2015/3), s. 239-246 ISSN 1642-3267 Jacek Wojtysiak John Paul II Catholic University of Lublin The Paradox of the stone and two concepts of omnipotence Introduction The history of science

More information

Wittgenstein s Logical Atomism. Seminar 8 PHIL2120 Topics in Analytic Philosophy 16 November 2012

Wittgenstein s Logical Atomism. Seminar 8 PHIL2120 Topics in Analytic Philosophy 16 November 2012 Wittgenstein s Logical Atomism Seminar 8 PHIL2120 Topics in Analytic Philosophy 16 November 2012 1 Admin Required reading for this seminar: Soames, Ch 9+10 New Schedule: 23 November: The Tractarian Test

More information

SIMON BOSTOCK Internal Properties and Property Realism

SIMON BOSTOCK Internal Properties and Property Realism SIMON BOSTOCK Internal Properties and Property Realism R ealism about properties, standardly, is contrasted with nominalism. According to nominalism, only particulars exist. According to realism, both

More information

Speaking My Mind: Expression and Self-Knowledge by Dorit Bar-On

Speaking My Mind: Expression and Self-Knowledge by Dorit Bar-On Speaking My Mind: Expression and Self-Knowledge by Dorit Bar-On Self-ascriptions of mental states, whether in speech or thought, seem to have a unique status. Suppose I make an utterance of the form I

More information

Putnam: Meaning and Reference

Putnam: Meaning and Reference Putnam: Meaning and Reference The Traditional Conception of Meaning combines two assumptions: Meaning and psychology Knowing the meaning (of a word, sentence) is being in a psychological state. Even Frege,

More information

Aboutness and Justification

Aboutness and Justification For a symposium on Imogen Dickie s book Fixing Reference to be published in Philosophy and Phenomenological Research. Aboutness and Justification Dilip Ninan dilip.ninan@tufts.edu September 2016 Al believes

More information

Theories of epistemic justification can be divided into two groups: internalist and

Theories of epistemic justification can be divided into two groups: internalist and 1 Internalism and externalism about justification Theories of epistemic justification can be divided into two groups: internalist and externalist. Internalist theories of justification say that whatever

More information

Semantic Foundations for Deductive Methods

Semantic Foundations for Deductive Methods Semantic Foundations for Deductive Methods delineating the scope of deductive reason Roger Bishop Jones Abstract. The scope of deductive reason is considered. First a connection is discussed between the

More information