Philosophical Writings Vol. 43 No.1 HOW NOT TO NATURALISE ACTION

Size: px
Start display at page:

Download "Philosophical Writings Vol. 43 No.1 HOW NOT TO NATURALISE ACTION"

Transcription

1 Philosophical Writings Vol. 43 No.1 Special Issue: Proceedings of the British Post-Graduate Philosophy Association Annual Conference 2014 HOW NOT TO NATURALISE ACTION University College London Abstract: The standard story of action the attempt to analyse action, or intentional action, in terms of mental causation has long been beset by the problem of so-called deviant causal chains. In fact, these present a challenge to all theorists standard or otherwise who want to understand the connection between an agent s desires, intentions and beliefs on the one hand, and their actions on the other, as a causalexplanatory one. I argue that the proper resolution of this problem involves understanding the mental states at issue as dispositions characteristically manifested in intentional or goal-directed action, so that the intentional non-intentional distinction maps more or less cleanly onto the manifestation non-manifestation distinction. Because dispositions are defined in terms of their characteristic manifestations, though, this means that the states in question are not explanatorily or ontologically prior to goal-directed action and are themselves to be understood in teleological terms. I argue on this basis that a standard story -type analysis cannot succeed as a naturalising or reductive account of the nature of intentional action (or, a fortiori, of action). Keywords: intentional action, mental causation, mental states, dispositions, causal action Date Submitted: 26/09/2014 Date Accepted: 02/11/2014 Vol. 43 pp

2 HOW NOT TO NATURALISE ACTION 1. Introduction Some philosophers are concerned about how to find a place for action in the explanatory order of the world (Velleman, 1992, 465). The problem is often framed using Wittgenstein s question, what is left over if I subtract the fact that my arm goes up from the fact that I raise my arm? (1968, 621), inviting the thought that the challenge is to work out what needs to be added to an arm-rising in order to make it into an arm-raising. 1 One influential approach has been to claim that something such as an arm s going up constitutes an action in virtue of being caused by certain mental states of the agent. As Velleman characterises the theory, it says that There is something that the agent wants, and there is an action that he believes is conducive to its attainment. His desire and his belief jointly cause an intention to take [the action], which in turn causes the corresponding movements of the agent s body. (Velleman, 1992, 461) Such a conception of the nature of action has been so influential that it has come to be known as the standard story. In this paper, I will address a variant of the standard story, namely the causal theory of intentional action, understood as an attempt to reductively analyse intentional action in terms of prior concepts of action, causation, and mental states. As I understand it, such a theory aims to (at least partly) naturalise intentional action: to explain how it fits into the efficient-causal order of things; specifically, to analyse it without reference to final causes. I ll argue that the causal theory is not the right means to that end. My argument is simple: the best treatment of deviant causal chains, a problem that has dogged all theories of this sort, involves understanding the mental states at issue as dispositions that are characteristically manifested in intentional, or at least goal-directed, action. Such a conception of these mental states is independently plausible, but is made especially attractive by its power to resolve the problem of causal deviance. However, since dispositions are defined in terms of their manifestation, these states are not ontologically or conceptually prior to goaldirected action, and must themselves be understood teleologically. So, if intentional 1 It was not, I take it, Wittgenstein s intention to invite this thought. 34

3 How Not to Naturalise Action action is to be naturalised, it will not simply be in terms of being caused in the right way by these mental states. I will focus mainly on states of desire, but suggest that the argument will also apply to intention and belief. 2. Causal deviance One can formulate a variety of causal theories about action, with different targets in mind, and it s often unclear who exactly holds exactly which version. A whole array of causal theories, for instance, are attributed to Davidson, but often at the risk oversimplifying his views. Davidson argued that something is an action just in case it is intentional under some description (2001, essay 3), that someone acts intentionally just in case they act for a reason, and that when someone acts for a reason their action is caused by a suitable belief desire pair (2001, essay 1). However, he suggested in later work that such a causal relation could not provide a reductive account of what it is to act intentionally (2001, essay 4). Many philosophers inspired by Davidson, however, do think that a reductive causal analysis is available. One much-discussed kind of account aims to analyse action in terms of bodily movement, claiming that bodily movements constitute actions in virtue of being suitably caused. Views of that kind won t be my primary target, but my arguments should apply to them a fortiori. 2 My target is the somewhat less ambitious attempt to analyse intentional action in causal terms. A theory of this sort can take action as primitive and claim that what makes an action intentional is being caused by the relevant mental states. If the primitive actionconcept is non-teleological then intentional action will have been, at least for our purposes, naturalised. 3 As it stands, though, even this causal theory is only schematic. If it is to provide a non-circular analysis of its target, and to reduce final to efficient causes, it must be more specific. First, it must specify what sorts of mental states or events are the right ones to cause an action so as to make it intentional. This is fairly simple. The right kinds of states are typically taken to be desire, intention or belief. They will 2 See e.g. Hornsby (2004) for criticism of the standard story ; Hornsby (1997, pt. 2), Owen (1980) for problems regarding bodily movements 3 One example of a non-teleological account of action is that given in Alvarez and Hyman (1998). Setiya (2009) appears to favour a reduction of intentional action along these lines. 35

4 also have to be states with contents relevant to the action in question, such as intentions to perform that action or to achieve some further end served by the action, or desires for some goal and beliefs about how to achieve it. In Davidson's terms, they must be states that rationalise the action. The second gap for the causal theorist to fill is to say what it is for the states to cause the action in the right way. This is rather more difficult, because of the problem of deviant causal chains the reason why we talk about the right kind of causation in the first place. It has long been recognised that whatever mental states you plug into the formula, it s possible to construct cases in which the states cause the agent to perform an action of the appropriate sort, but cause it in the wrong way such that the action is unintentional. The classic example is Davidson s: A climber might want to rid himself of the weight and danger of holding another man on a rope, and he might know that by loosening his hold on the rope he could rid himself of the weight and danger. This belief and want might so unnerve him as to cause him to loosen his hold, and yet it might be the case that he never chose to loosen his hold, nor did he do it intentionally. (2001, 79) Similar cases can be constructed for states of belief and intention. The import of such examples is that if a causal account of intentional action is to be given, we need to be able to specify in a principled way what the right kind of causation is, so as to rule such cases out in a non-circular, non-ad hoc fashion. Many attempts at this task have been made, but, up until now, none has been ultimately satisfactory. 4 Thankfully, recent work on dispositions offers a novel and plausible solution to the problem. As we shall see, however, it's no solution for our causal theorist. 3. Desire & dispositions We can begin approaching a resolution of the problem of deviant causation by noting the grounds on which we actually distinguish right from wrong causal chains. It's a matter of teleology. We judge that Davidson s climber s action wasn t caused in the right way by their desire because we judge that the climber doesn t 4 Mayr (2011, chap. 5) gives an overview; see also e.g. Sehon (1997). 36

5 How Not to Naturalise Action loosen their hold with the aim of ridding themselves of the weight and danger. This notion of acting with an aim is exactly the one that our causalist wants to naturalise. The causal theorist, then, has to assume that the right kind of causation can be specified without appeal to this notion. But unfortunately (for them), the most promising specification of caused in the right way succeeds precisely by retaining this teleological idea. Hyman, in a recent paper drawing from contemporary work on the metaphysics of dispositions, argues that the problem of deviant causation can be resolved as follows. Desires are dispositions of agents, and an agent s action is caused in the right way by a desire just in case it is a manifestation, rather than a mere symptom, of that disposition. Since dispositions are defined in terms of their manifestation, the criterion for right causation is given in the definition of desire. 5 Hyman s proposed (rough) definition is that a desire is a disposition manifested in two main ways: first, by purposive or goal-directed behaviour, specifically, behaviour aimed at satisfying the desire, in other words, at getting what it is a desire to have, or doing what it is a desire to do; and second, by feeling glad, pleased or relieved if the desire is satisfied, and sorry, displeased or disappointed if it is frustrated. (2013, 3) Explanations of action in terms of desire are causal because desires, as dispositions, are causal factors: an explanation of an action in terms of a desire is of the same general sort as one of a glass's shattering in terms of its brittleness. If we understand desires in this way, then the problem of deviant causation is shown not to be a special problem for the analysis of intentional action, but rather an instance of the general problem of reducing the manifestation of dispositions to causal chains of events. [W]ith certain exceptions, argues Hyman, every disposition can be connected to the kind of occurrence that normally manifests it by a deviant or freakish causal chain (2013, 12). He gives the following example: A man might take a soporific drug before driving, and the drowsiness induced by the drug might make him crash the car and knock himself unconscious. If this happened, he would lose consciousness because he took the drug, but the exercise of its virtus dormitiva would be preempted by the crash. (2013, 12) 5 See Wittgenstein (1969, 245) for the distinction between symptoms and criteria of dispositions. 37

6 Many similar examples can be given. Indeed, Davidson s climber is an example of the same sort: the climber s dropping his companion is caused by a mere symptom of his desire to rid himself of the weight, namely his nervousness at having such a desire; it is caused by the desire, but does not manifest the desire. Had the climber dropped his partner intentionally, he would have dropped him with the aim of ridding himself of the weight, and his action would thus have manifested his desire to rid himself of the weight, and so been caused in the right way by the desire. Hyman s account, then, gives us a principled way to distinguish right from wrong causation: an action is caused by a desire in the right way to make it intentional only when the action manifests the desire and is done with the aim of satisfying the desire. Hyman's account of desire seems to me basically correct, but it s beyond the scope of this paper to offer a full defence of it. That said, I think we have already seen one significant point in its favour, namely that it enables us to give a straightforward explanation of the proper causal connection between a desire and an action done with the aim of satisfying that desire. The right kind of causation is a matter of the action s manifesting the desire. This is significant progress although not towards the kind of analysis envisioned by the causal theorist. I ve suggested that we can specify a type of causal connection between mental state and action that is not subject to deviant causal chains. This seems to be pretty good evidence that this is the connection we are after that it is the right kind of causation. It shouldn t be surprising that identifying the right connection between state and action was in part a matter of giving an account of the nature of the relevant states. Our problem, after all, was how states (of a certain kind) cause actions (in the right way). How a type of state can cause an action obviously depends on what the state itself is like. With this in mind, it's perhaps surprising how easily the question of the nature of these states tends to be brushed over in discussion of the standard story. 6 We're now in a position to say something decisive about the unfilled gaps in the causal theory. However, we don't end up with a naturalising or reductive account of intentional action. The theory we get is that desires are dispositions 6 Cf. Steward (1997). 38

7 How Not to Naturalise Action characteristically manifested in, among certain other things, actions aimed at satisfying the desire. Dispositions are defined in terms of their characteristic manifestation so, on the present view, desire is defined in terms of goal-directed action a teleological notion. The right kind of causation is a kind of final causation. Moreover desire is, on this view, ontologically dependent on goal-directed action: what it is to desire to φ depends upon what it is to do something with the aim of φ- ing. 7 So an analysis in which desire occurs in the analysans has not reduced final to efficient causes. It might be tempting to think that we could get back to a naturalising theory by eliminating the notion of goal-directed action from the definition of desire, replacing it with bodily movement, or with action (unqualified). Since desires would then be dispositions defined in part in terms of (unqualified) actions, we would seem to have the potential for a naturalising account that defined intentional actions as just those actions that manifest desires. Unfortunately that won t do. For one thing, it doesn t look like an adequate account of desire, since in eliminating goal-directedness from the definition of desire, you eliminate your own ability to explain why desires explain actions. Why do you go downstairs when you hear the knock? Because of your desire to find out who is at the door, which is a disposition to what? A disposition to do certain things in certain circumstances, perhaps. But why are you disposed to act in these ways in these circumstances? Because these actions seem to you to be a means to finding out who is at the door. If our aim is to eliminate the placeholders ( right kind etc.) from our theory of action, we haven t succeeded by shifting those placeholders into our definition of one of the key terms in that theory. For much the same reason, eliminating goal-directedness from the definition of the disposition eliminates our ability to make a principled distinction between right and wrong causal chains. The dispositional account of desire enables us to make this distinction in a principled way because dispositions are defined in terms of their characteristic manifestations. The distinction between an action caused in the right way and one caused in the wrong way just is the distinction between a manifestation and a symptom of the state. The reason it distinguishes intentional actions from unintentional actions or mere bodily movements is that the state is manifested in the 7 See Kalderon (2012) on the notion of ontological dependence. 39

8 former and not in the latter. If the desire to rid myself of my companion s weight is, say, a disposition to do things that seem conducive to ridding myself of the weight, rather than a disposition to do things with the aim of ridding myself of the weight, then I could in principle manifest that desire by dropping my companion without doing so intentionally. The account would thus fail to close the door on deviant causal chains. 4. Intention & belief I ve so far only discussed the attempt to analyse intentional action in terms of desire. The very fact that the problem of deviant causation crops up just as readily for belief and intention as it does for desire in itself suggests, in light of the points already made, that belief and intention should also be understood in dispositional terms. However, given that causal theories commonly appeal not only to desire but to belief and intention too, a full account of where those theories go wrong will need to directly address these states as well. To show how this might be done, I'll now make some brief suggestions about how intention and belief might be understood as dispositions manifested in the kind of action the causalist wants to explain. It seems likely that in so far as there is a kind of mental state called intention that causes intentional actions, it will look very much like desire, at least on the broad philosophical conception of desire that we've been working with. Of course intention has special features that desires in general lack. On one account, intentions are states that an agent can form by making a decision to perform the relevant action, which (unless revised) will lead the agent to perform the action directly (Holton, 2009, 2), and which are stable, in the sense that they have a tendency to persist once formed. We might add that an intention to φ won t only lead the agent to φ if they happen to be lucky enough to end up in a position to φ, but will also lead them to take steps that seem conducive to their getting into such a position. My intention to make a cake is expressed just as directly in my buying flour as it is in my creaming the butter and sugar. Generally, your intention to achieve some end motivates you to take the means to that end as well as to consummate the end. Given these observations, it's plausible that the definition of intention will have a certain amount of overlap with that of desire: an intention to φ is at least in part a (stable) 40

9 How Not to Naturalise Action disposition to φ, which can (but needn't) be formed by deciding to φ, and which is manifested in behaviour aimed at φ-ing (including the act of φ-ing itself). This (partial) definition, like that of desire, involves the notion of goal-directed action, and as such it is no more suitable for a naturalistic account of intentional action. There may be a lot more that we want to say about the nature of intention, but none of it seems likely to overturn this point. Belief needs to be treated slightly differently, not least because belief is best suited for a slightly different sort of causal theory. The concepts of acting intentionally and acting for a reason are often conflated, but they ought not to be (see Alvarez, 2009), and the notion of belief is clearly more intimately connected with the latter than with the former. Belief seems more appropriate to be employed in a causal theory of acting for a reason or, better, acting on a ground 8 than of acting intentionally. When one acts on a belief, one s belief (i.e., the thing one believes) is the ground on which one acts. As before, it s tempting to say that what makes it the case that one acts on the ground that p is that one s action is caused in the right way by one s belief (i.e., one s state of believing) that p. And as before, deviant causation rears its ugly head. (It should be easy enough to see how; I won t bore you with examples.) Again, I suggest that the solution is to define belief as a disposition manifested in the relevant kind of action: to believe that p is, at least in part, to be disposed to do things on the ground that p (where do things covers thought and feeling as well as bodily action, and the ground that p is non-factive). If that s correct, then the right kind of causation to connect a belief to an action done on grounds of the content of that belief is straightforwardly analogous to the one for desire: the action is caused in the right way when it manifests the belief in question. Again we don t have a naturalising analysis, because again the mental state in question is defined in terms of the thing the causalist wanted to naturalise, namely (in this case) the notion of acting on grounds. 8 I say ground because I take reason, or at least one important sense of reason, to be factive. A ground here is the sort of thing one can act on even when, as it turns out, one is mistaken. 41

10 5. Conclusion Where do we go from here? We ve seen good reason to think that an analysis of intentional action in terms of causation in the right way by desire attempts to analyse intentional action in terms of something desire which is not more fundamental than intentional (or at least goal-directed) action, and which is (derivatively) teleological in nature. We ve also seen that matters are likely much the same with respect to the states of intention and belief. Is there any hope, then, for fitting intentional action into the efficient-causal natural order? The intimate connection between intentional actions and, on the one hand, actions simpliciter and, on the other, mental states, made it seem that the causation of actions by states was the most promising way to explain intentional action in terms that appeared more naturalistically tractable. This thought looks to have been misguided. What, then, should we say about the project of naturalising intentional action? One point to note is about mental states. We ve seen that defining desire as a kind of disposition manifested in goal-directed action provides a strong solution to the problem of deviant causal chains. This seems like pretty good evidence that such a definition is correct. I ve also suggested that similar accounts may be given for belief and intention. Such analyses explain why we make an intuitive distinction between right and wrong causal chains, and also explain how action-explanation in terms of those states is causal as well as teleological (or rational in the case of belief). These accounts, if correct, have significant implications for the project of naturalising the mental. Perhaps most notably, they show that finding a place for these states in a naturalistic worldview will depend in part on doing the same for dispositions and powers in general. A second point a suggestion, really is that properly naturalising the mental phenomena discussed here will not be a matter for simplistic conceptual analysis. The mental states of interest are typed partly in terms of their connection with intentional action, but it also seems doubtful that we could make sense of the idea of intentional action in the absence of such states. It looks as if they all come as a package. I see no reason to think that any of these mental concepts should be reducible to any of the others. However, there also seems little reason to doubt that just as we can cast light on the dispositions of inanimate objects by 42

11 How Not to Naturalise Action investigating their structure, constitution, and so on these particular dispositions (desire, intention, belief) of objects of this particular kind (human agents), as well as their characteristic manifestation in goal-directed behaviour, will be illuminated by just the sort of work currently being undertaken in cognitive science and the philosophy of cognitive science. In particular, naturalistically-inclined work on mental content, action-guiding representations and the like look like much more promising avenues for understanding how intentional action and the mental states that it manifests fit into the explanatory order of the world than the causal theory of action does. I don t know whether we should expect intentional action to be reduced through such work, but we can certainly hope to learn a lot more about how it works than we ever did from the standard story. So, to conclude: naturalising action isn't as straightforward as the causalist envisaged but we can at least see a way forward. edgar.phillips.13@ucl.ac.uk REFERENCES Alvarez, M. (2009). Acting intentionally and acting for a reason. Inquiry, 52(3): Alvarez, M. & Hyman, J. (1998). Agents and their actions. Philosophy, 73(2): Davidson, D. (2001). Essays on Actions and Events (2nd ed.). Oxford: Oxford University Press. Holton, R. (2009). Willing, Wanting, Waiting. Oxford: Oxford University Press. Hornsby, J. (1997). Simple Mindedness: In Defense of Naive Naturalism in the Philosophy of Mind. Cambridge, Mass.: Harvard University Press. Hornsby, J. (2004). Agency and actions. In J. Hyman & H. Steward (eds.), Agency and Action (1 23). Cambridge: Cambridge University Press. Hyman, J. (2013). Desires, dispositions and deviant causal chains. Philosophy 89(1): Kalderon, M. (2012). Experiential pluralism and the power of perception [PDF document]. Retrieved from: erception Mayr, E. (2011). Understanding Human Agency. Oxford: Oxford University Press. 43

12 Owen, D. W. D. (1980). Actions and bodily movements: Another move. Analysis 40(1): Sehon, S. R. (1997). Deviant causal chains and the irreducibility of teleological explanation. Pacific Philosophical Quarterly 78(2): Setiya, K. (2009). Reasons and causes. European Journal of Philosophy 19(1): Steward, H. (1997). The Ontology of Mind: Events, Processes, and States. Oxford: Clarendon Press. Velleman, J. D. (1992). What happens when someone acts? Mind 101(403): Wittgenstein, L. (1968). Philosophical Investigations (3rd ed. G. E. M. Anscombe, Trans.). Oxford: Basil Blackwell. Wittgenstein, L. (1969). The Blue and Brown Books: Preliminary Studies for the Philosophical Investigations (2nd ed.). Oxford: Basil Blackwell. 44

A New Argument Against Compatibilism

A New Argument Against Compatibilism Norwegian University of Life Sciences School of Economics and Business A New Argument Against Compatibilism Stephen Mumford and Rani Lill Anjum Working Papers No. 2/ 2014 ISSN: 2464-1561 A New Argument

More information

Reasons With Rationalism After All MICHAEL SMITH

Reasons With Rationalism After All MICHAEL SMITH book symposium 521 Bratman, M.E. Forthcoming a. Intention, belief, practical, theoretical. In Spheres of Reason: New Essays on the Philosophy of Normativity, ed. Simon Robertson. Oxford: Oxford University

More information

proper construal of Davidson s principle of rationality will show the objection to be misguided. Andrew Wong Washington University, St.

proper construal of Davidson s principle of rationality will show the objection to be misguided. Andrew Wong Washington University, St. Do e s An o m a l o u s Mo n i s m Hav e Explanatory Force? Andrew Wong Washington University, St. Louis The aim of this paper is to support Donald Davidson s Anomalous Monism 1 as an account of law-governed

More information

EVERYBODY NEEDS TO KNOW?

EVERYBODY NEEDS TO KNOW? EVERYBODY NEEDS TO KNOW? This reader came away from Sosa s Judgment and Agency with the poignant impression of an otherwise sophisticated and compelling view encumbered by an implausible central element.

More information

Moral requirements are still not rational requirements

Moral requirements are still not rational requirements ANALYSIS 59.3 JULY 1999 Moral requirements are still not rational requirements Paul Noordhof According to Michael Smith, the Rationalist makes the following conceptual claim. If it is right for agents

More information

How Many Kinds of Reasons? (Pre-print November 2008) Introduction

How Many Kinds of Reasons? (Pre-print November 2008) Introduction How Many Kinds of Reasons? (Pre-print November 2008) Introduction My interest in the question that is the title of my paper is primarily as a means of preparing the ground, and the conceptual tools, for

More information

Wright on response-dependence and self-knowledge

Wright on response-dependence and self-knowledge Wright on response-dependence and self-knowledge March 23, 2004 1 Response-dependent and response-independent concepts........... 1 1.1 The intuitive distinction......................... 1 1.2 Basic equations

More information

Aboutness and Justification

Aboutness and Justification For a symposium on Imogen Dickie s book Fixing Reference to be published in Philosophy and Phenomenological Research. Aboutness and Justification Dilip Ninan dilip.ninan@tufts.edu September 2016 Al believes

More information

Stout s teleological theory of action

Stout s teleological theory of action Stout s teleological theory of action Jeff Speaks November 26, 2004 1 The possibility of externalist explanations of action................ 2 1.1 The distinction between externalist and internalist explanations

More information

DO TROPES RESOLVE THE PROBLEM OF MENTAL CAUSATION?

DO TROPES RESOLVE THE PROBLEM OF MENTAL CAUSATION? DO TROPES RESOLVE THE PROBLEM OF MENTAL CAUSATION? 221 DO TROPES RESOLVE THE PROBLEM OF MENTAL CAUSATION? BY PAUL NOORDHOF One of the reasons why the problem of mental causation appears so intractable

More information

Right-Making, Reference, and Reduction

Right-Making, Reference, and Reduction Right-Making, Reference, and Reduction Kent State University BIBLID [0873-626X (2014) 39; pp. 139-145] Abstract The causal theory of reference (CTR) provides a well-articulated and widely-accepted account

More information

Are There Reasons to Be Rational?

Are There Reasons to Be Rational? Are There Reasons to Be Rational? Olav Gjelsvik, University of Oslo The thesis. Among people writing about rationality, few people are more rational than Wlodek Rabinowicz. But are there reasons for being

More information

Why there is no such thing as a motivating reason

Why there is no such thing as a motivating reason Why there is no such thing as a motivating reason Benjamin Kiesewetter, ENN Meeting in Oslo, 03.11.2016 (ERS) Explanatory reason statement: R is the reason why p. (NRS) Normative reason statement: R is

More information

Can Rationality Be Naturalistically Explained? Jeffrey Dunn. Abstract: Dan Chiappe and John Vervaeke (1997) conclude their article, Fodor,

Can Rationality Be Naturalistically Explained? Jeffrey Dunn. Abstract: Dan Chiappe and John Vervaeke (1997) conclude their article, Fodor, Can Rationality Be Naturalistically Explained? Jeffrey Dunn Abstract: Dan Chiappe and John Vervaeke (1997) conclude their article, Fodor, Cherniak and the Naturalization of Rationality, with an argument

More information

Why I Am Not a Property Dualist By John R. Searle

Why I Am Not a Property Dualist By John R. Searle 1 Why I Am Not a Property Dualist By John R. Searle I have argued in a number of writings 1 that the philosophical part (though not the neurobiological part) of the traditional mind-body problem has a

More information

A Contrast between Two Pictures : The Case of Perception

A Contrast between Two Pictures : The Case of Perception A Contrast between Two Pictures : The Case of Perception Jennifer Hornsby Birkbeck, University of London, and C.S.M.N., University of Oslo. Frederick Stoutland s 1 early work in philosophy of action was

More information

TWO ACCOUNTS OF THE NORMATIVITY OF RATIONALITY

TWO ACCOUNTS OF THE NORMATIVITY OF RATIONALITY DISCUSSION NOTE BY JONATHAN WAY JOURNAL OF ETHICS & SOCIAL PHILOSOPHY DISCUSSION NOTE DECEMBER 2009 URL: WWW.JESP.ORG COPYRIGHT JONATHAN WAY 2009 Two Accounts of the Normativity of Rationality RATIONALITY

More information

DISCUSSION THE GUISE OF A REASON

DISCUSSION THE GUISE OF A REASON NADEEM J.Z. HUSSAIN DISCUSSION THE GUISE OF A REASON The articles collected in David Velleman s The Possibility of Practical Reason are a snapshot or rather a film-strip of part of a philosophical endeavour

More information

AGENCY AND THE A-SERIES. Roman Altshuler SUNY Stony Brook

AGENCY AND THE A-SERIES. Roman Altshuler SUNY Stony Brook AGENCY AND THE A-SERIES Roman Altshuler SUNY Stony Brook Following McTaggart s distinction of two series the A-series and the B- series according to which we understand time, much of the debate in the

More information

Philosophical Review.

Philosophical Review. Philosophical Review Review: [untitled] Author(s): Katalin Balog Source: The Philosophical Review, Vol. 108, No. 4 (Oct., 1999), pp. 562-565 Published by: Duke University Press on behalf of Philosophical

More information

8 Internal and external reasons

8 Internal and external reasons ioo Rawls and Pascal's wager out how under-powered the supposed rational choice under ignorance is. Rawls' theory tries, in effect, to link politics with morality, and morality (or at least the relevant

More information

British Journal for the Philosophy of Science, 62 (2011), doi: /bjps/axr026

British Journal for the Philosophy of Science, 62 (2011), doi: /bjps/axr026 British Journal for the Philosophy of Science, 62 (2011), 899-907 doi:10.1093/bjps/axr026 URL: Please cite published version only. REVIEW

More information

World without Design: The Ontological Consequences of Natural- ism , by Michael C. Rea.

World without Design: The Ontological Consequences of Natural- ism , by Michael C. Rea. Book reviews World without Design: The Ontological Consequences of Naturalism, by Michael C. Rea. Oxford: Clarendon Press, 2004, viii + 245 pp., $24.95. This is a splendid book. Its ideas are bold and

More information

Shieva Kleinschmidt [This is a draft I completed while at Rutgers. Please do not cite without permission.] Conditional Desires.

Shieva Kleinschmidt [This is a draft I completed while at Rutgers. Please do not cite without permission.] Conditional Desires. Shieva Kleinschmidt [This is a draft I completed while at Rutgers. Please do not cite without permission.] Conditional Desires Abstract: There s an intuitive distinction between two types of desires: conditional

More information

EXTERNALISM AND THE CONTENT OF MORAL MOTIVATION

EXTERNALISM AND THE CONTENT OF MORAL MOTIVATION EXTERNALISM AND THE CONTENT OF MORAL MOTIVATION Caj Strandberg Department of Philosophy, Lund University and Gothenburg University Caj.Strandberg@fil.lu.se ABSTRACT: Michael Smith raises in his fetishist

More information

Postmodal Metaphysics

Postmodal Metaphysics Postmodal Metaphysics Ted Sider Structuralism seminar 1. Conceptual tools in metaphysics Tools of metaphysics : concepts for framing metaphysical issues. They structure metaphysical discourse. Problem

More information

Rule-Following and the Ontology of the Mind Abstract The problem of rule-following

Rule-Following and the Ontology of the Mind Abstract The problem of rule-following Rule-Following and the Ontology of the Mind Michael Esfeld (published in Uwe Meixner and Peter Simons (eds.): Metaphysics in the Post-Metaphysical Age. Papers of the 22nd International Wittgenstein Symposium.

More information

Rationality in Action. By John Searle. Cambridge: MIT Press, pages, ISBN Hardback $35.00.

Rationality in Action. By John Searle. Cambridge: MIT Press, pages, ISBN Hardback $35.00. 106 AUSLEGUNG Rationality in Action. By John Searle. Cambridge: MIT Press, 2001. 303 pages, ISBN 0-262-19463-5. Hardback $35.00. Curran F. Douglass University of Kansas John Searle's Rationality in Action

More information

Epistemological Foundations for Koons Cosmological Argument?

Epistemological Foundations for Koons Cosmological Argument? Epistemological Foundations for Koons Cosmological Argument? Koons (2008) argues for the very surprising conclusion that any exception to the principle of general causation [i.e., the principle that everything

More information

POWERS, NECESSITY, AND DETERMINISM

POWERS, NECESSITY, AND DETERMINISM POWERS, NECESSITY, AND DETERMINISM Thought 3:3 (2014): 225-229 ~Penultimate Draft~ The final publication is available at http://onlinelibrary.wiley.com/doi/10.1002/tht3.139/abstract Abstract: Stephen Mumford

More information

Projection in Hume. P J E Kail. St. Peter s College, Oxford.

Projection in Hume. P J E Kail. St. Peter s College, Oxford. Projection in Hume P J E Kail St. Peter s College, Oxford Peter.kail@spc.ox.ac.uk A while ago now (2007) I published my Projection and Realism in Hume s Philosophy (Oxford University Press henceforth abbreviated

More information

A solution to the problem of hijacked experience

A solution to the problem of hijacked experience A solution to the problem of hijacked experience Jill is not sure what Jack s current mood is, but she fears that he is angry with her. Then Jack steps into the room. Jill gets a good look at his face.

More information

FOREWORD: ADDRESSING THE HARD PROBLEM OF CONSCIOUSNESS

FOREWORD: ADDRESSING THE HARD PROBLEM OF CONSCIOUSNESS Biophysics of Consciousness: A Foundational Approach R. R. Poznanski, J. A. Tuszynski and T. E. Feinberg Copyright 2017 World Scientific, Singapore. FOREWORD: ADDRESSING THE HARD PROBLEM OF CONSCIOUSNESS

More information

Act individuation and basic acts

Act individuation and basic acts Act individuation and basic acts August 27, 2004 1 Arguments for a coarse-grained criterion of act-individuation........ 2 1.1 Argument from parsimony........................ 2 1.2 The problem of the relationship

More information

Different kinds of naturalistic explanations of linguistic behaviour

Different kinds of naturalistic explanations of linguistic behaviour Different kinds of naturalistic explanations of linguistic behaviour Manuel Bremer Abstract. Naturalistic explanations (of linguistic behaviour) have to answer two questions: What is meant by giving a

More information

Edinburgh Research Explorer

Edinburgh Research Explorer Edinburgh Research Explorer The Normativity of Mind-World Relations Citation for published version: Hazlett, A 2015, 'The Normativity of Mind-World Relations: Comments on Sosa' Episteme, vol. 12, no. 2,

More information

Agency, Ownership, and the Standard Theory

Agency, Ownership, and the Standard Theory Agency, Ownership, and the Standard Theory Markus E. Schlosser Forthcoming in J. Aguilar, A. Buckareff, and K. Frankish (eds.) New Waves in Philosophy of Action, Basingstoke: Macmillan This is the author

More information

PHENOMENALITY AND INTENTIONALITY WHICH EXPLAINS WHICH?: REPLY TO GERTLER

PHENOMENALITY AND INTENTIONALITY WHICH EXPLAINS WHICH?: REPLY TO GERTLER PHENOMENALITY AND INTENTIONALITY WHICH EXPLAINS WHICH?: REPLY TO GERTLER Department of Philosophy University of California, Riverside Riverside, CA 92521 U.S.A. siewert@ucr.edu Copyright (c) Charles Siewert

More information

PRACTICAL REASONING. Bart Streumer

PRACTICAL REASONING. Bart Streumer PRACTICAL REASONING Bart Streumer b.streumer@rug.nl In Timothy O Connor and Constantine Sandis (eds.), A Companion to the Philosophy of Action Published version available here: http://dx.doi.org/10.1002/9781444323528.ch31

More information

Reason and Explanation: A Defense of Explanatory Coherentism. BY TED POSTON (Basingstoke,

Reason and Explanation: A Defense of Explanatory Coherentism. BY TED POSTON (Basingstoke, Reason and Explanation: A Defense of Explanatory Coherentism. BY TED POSTON (Basingstoke, UK: Palgrave Macmillan, 2014. Pp. 208. Price 60.) In this interesting book, Ted Poston delivers an original and

More information

Agency: Humans, Animals and Objects. Thomas James Quinn

Agency: Humans, Animals and Objects. Thomas James Quinn Agency: Humans, Animals and Objects Thomas James Quinn Submitted for the degree of Doctor of Philosophy Birkbeck College, University of London April 2017 1 I hereby declare that the work contained in this

More information

Kantian Humility and Ontological Categories Sam Cowling University of Massachusetts, Amherst

Kantian Humility and Ontological Categories Sam Cowling University of Massachusetts, Amherst Kantian Humility and Ontological Categories Sam Cowling University of Massachusetts, Amherst [Forthcoming in Analysis. Penultimate Draft. Cite published version.] Kantian Humility holds that agents like

More information

CANADIAN JOURNAL OF PHILOSOPHY Supplementary Volume 35. Guidance and Belief

CANADIAN JOURNAL OF PHILOSOPHY Supplementary Volume 35. Guidance and Belief CANADIAN JOURNAL OF PHILOSOPHY Supplementary Volume 35 Guidance and Belief There is a difference between those things one does that manifest agency and those things that merely happen to one or that are

More information

Luminosity in the stream of consciousness

Luminosity in the stream of consciousness https://doi.org/10.1007/s11229-018-1801-0 S.I.: KNOWLEDGE AND JUSTIFICATION, NEW PERSPECTIVES Luminosity in the stream of consciousness David Jenkins 1 Received: 25 July 2017 / Accepted: 1 May 2018 The

More information

Moral Argumentation from a Rhetorical Point of View

Moral Argumentation from a Rhetorical Point of View Chapter 98 Moral Argumentation from a Rhetorical Point of View Lars Leeten Universität Hildesheim Practical thinking is a tricky business. Its aim will never be fulfilled unless influence on practical

More information

Two Kinds of Ends in Themselves in Kant s Moral Theory

Two Kinds of Ends in Themselves in Kant s Moral Theory Western University Scholarship@Western 2015 Undergraduate Awards The Undergraduate Awards 2015 Two Kinds of Ends in Themselves in Kant s Moral Theory David Hakim Western University, davidhakim266@gmail.com

More information

CONCEPT OF WILLING IN WITTGENSTEIN S PHILOSOPHICAL INVESTIGATIONS

CONCEPT OF WILLING IN WITTGENSTEIN S PHILOSOPHICAL INVESTIGATIONS 42 Philosophy and Progress Philosophy and Progress: Vols. LVII-LVIII, January-June, July-December, 2015 ISSN 1607-2278 (Print), DOI : http://dx.doi.org/10.3329/pp.v57il-2.31203 CONCEPT OF WILLING IN WITTGENSTEIN

More information

TWO VERSIONS OF HUME S LAW

TWO VERSIONS OF HUME S LAW DISCUSSION NOTE BY CAMPBELL BROWN JOURNAL OF ETHICS & SOCIAL PHILOSOPHY DISCUSSION NOTE MAY 2015 URL: WWW.JESP.ORG COPYRIGHT CAMPBELL BROWN 2015 Two Versions of Hume s Law MORAL CONCLUSIONS CANNOT VALIDLY

More information

Skepticism and Internalism

Skepticism and Internalism Skepticism and Internalism John Greco Abstract: This paper explores a familiar skeptical problematic and considers some strategies for responding to it. Section 1 reconstructs and disambiguates the skeptical

More information

Luck, Rationality, and Explanation: A Reply to Elga s Lucky to Be Rational. Joshua Schechter. Brown University

Luck, Rationality, and Explanation: A Reply to Elga s Lucky to Be Rational. Joshua Schechter. Brown University Luck, Rationality, and Explanation: A Reply to Elga s Lucky to Be Rational Joshua Schechter Brown University I Introduction What is the epistemic significance of discovering that one of your beliefs depends

More information

Virtuous act, virtuous dispositions

Virtuous act, virtuous dispositions virtuous act, virtuous dispositions 69 Virtuous act, virtuous dispositions Thomas Hurka Everyday moral thought uses the concepts of virtue and vice at two different levels. At what I will call a global

More information

Review of David J. Chalmers Constructing the World (OUP 2012) David Chalmers burst onto the philosophical scene in the mid-1990s with his work on

Review of David J. Chalmers Constructing the World (OUP 2012) David Chalmers burst onto the philosophical scene in the mid-1990s with his work on Review of David J. Chalmers Constructing the World (OUP 2012) Thomas W. Polger, University of Cincinnati 1. Introduction David Chalmers burst onto the philosophical scene in the mid-1990s with his work

More information

Craig on the Experience of Tense

Craig on the Experience of Tense Craig on the Experience of Tense In his recent book, The Tensed Theory of Time: A Critical Examination, 1 William Lane Craig offers several criticisms of my views on our experience of time. The purpose

More information

Each copy of any part of a JSTOR transmission must contain the same copyright notice that appears on the screen or printed page of such transmission.

Each copy of any part of a JSTOR transmission must contain the same copyright notice that appears on the screen or printed page of such transmission. The Physical World Author(s): Barry Stroud Source: Proceedings of the Aristotelian Society, New Series, Vol. 87 (1986-1987), pp. 263-277 Published by: Blackwell Publishing on behalf of The Aristotelian

More information

Philosophical Perspectives, 16, Language and Mind, 2002 THE AIM OF BELIEF 1. Ralph Wedgwood Merton College, Oxford

Philosophical Perspectives, 16, Language and Mind, 2002 THE AIM OF BELIEF 1. Ralph Wedgwood Merton College, Oxford Philosophical Perspectives, 16, Language and Mind, 2002 THE AIM OF BELIEF 1 Ralph Wedgwood Merton College, Oxford 0. Introduction It is often claimed that beliefs aim at the truth. Indeed, this claim has

More information

Spinoza, the No Shared Attribute thesis, and the

Spinoza, the No Shared Attribute thesis, and the Spinoza, the No Shared Attribute thesis, and the Principle of Sufficient Reason * Daniel Whiting This is a pre-print of an article whose final and definitive form is due to be published in the British

More information

The Question of Metaphysics

The Question of Metaphysics The Question of Metaphysics metaphysics seriously. Second, I want to argue that the currently popular hands-off conception of metaphysical theorising is unable to provide a satisfactory answer to the question

More information

New Aristotelianism, Routledge, 2012), in which he expanded upon

New Aristotelianism, Routledge, 2012), in which he expanded upon Powers, Essentialism and Agency: A Reply to Alexander Bird Ruth Porter Groff, Saint Louis University AUB Conference, April 28-29, 2016 1. Here s the backstory. A couple of years ago my friend Alexander

More information

Journal for the History of Analytical Philosophy Volume 3, Number 9

Journal for the History of Analytical Philosophy Volume 3, Number 9 Journal for the History of Analytical Philosophy Volume 3, Number 9 Editor in Chief Kevin C. Klement, University of Massachusetts Editorial Board Gary Ebbs, Indiana University Bloomington Greg Frost-Arnold,

More information

In his paper Internal Reasons, Michael Smith argues that the internalism

In his paper Internal Reasons, Michael Smith argues that the internalism Aporia vol. 18 no. 1 2008 Why Prefer a System of Desires? Ja s o n A. Hills In his paper Internal Reasons, Michael Smith argues that the internalism requirement on a theory of reasons involves what a fully

More information

Realism and instrumentalism

Realism and instrumentalism Published in H. Pashler (Ed.) The Encyclopedia of the Mind (2013), Thousand Oaks, CA: SAGE Publications, pp. 633 636 doi:10.4135/9781452257044 mark.sprevak@ed.ac.uk Realism and instrumentalism Mark Sprevak

More information

Life, Automata and the Mind-Body Problem

Life, Automata and the Mind-Body Problem TEL-AVIV UNIVERSITY LESTER & SALLY ENTIN FACULTY OF HUMANTIES THE SCHOOL OF PHILOSOPHY Life, Automata and the Mind-Body Problem Thesis Submitted for the Degree of Doctor of Philosophy by Vered Glickman

More information

Quine s Naturalized Epistemology, Epistemic Normativity and the. Gettier Problem

Quine s Naturalized Epistemology, Epistemic Normativity and the. Gettier Problem Quine s Naturalized Epistemology, Epistemic Normativity and the Gettier Problem Dr. Qilin Li (liqilin@gmail.com; liqilin@pku.edu.cn) The Department of Philosophy, Peking University Beiijing, P. R. China

More information

Review: The Objects of Thought, by Tim Crane. Guy Longworth University of Warwick

Review: The Objects of Thought, by Tim Crane. Guy Longworth University of Warwick Review: The Objects of Thought, by Tim Crane. Guy Longworth University of Warwick 24.4.14 We can think about things that don t exist. For example, we can think about Pegasus, and Pegasus doesn t exist.

More information

Perception and Mind-Dependence: Lecture 2

Perception and Mind-Dependence: Lecture 2 1 Recap Perception and Mind-Dependence: Lecture 2 (Alex Moran, apm60@ cam.ac.uk) According to naïve realism: (1) the objects of perception are ordinary, mindindependent things, and (2) perceptual experience

More information

KNOWLEDGE ON AFFECTIVE TRUST. Arnon Keren

KNOWLEDGE ON AFFECTIVE TRUST. Arnon Keren Abstracta SPECIAL ISSUE VI, pp. 33 46, 2012 KNOWLEDGE ON AFFECTIVE TRUST Arnon Keren Epistemologists of testimony widely agree on the fact that our reliance on other people's testimony is extensive. However,

More information

Divine omniscience, timelessness, and the power to do otherwise

Divine omniscience, timelessness, and the power to do otherwise Religious Studies 42, 123 139 f 2006 Cambridge University Press doi:10.1017/s0034412506008250 Printed in the United Kingdom Divine omniscience, timelessness, and the power to do otherwise HUGH RICE Christ

More information

(P420-1) Practical Reason in Ancient Greek and Contemporary Philosophy. Spring 2018

(P420-1) Practical Reason in Ancient Greek and Contemporary Philosophy. Spring 2018 (P420-1) Practical Reason in Ancient Greek and Contemporary Philosophy Course Instructor: Spring 2018 NAME Dr Evgenia Mylonaki EMAIL evgenia_mil@hotmail.com; emylonaki@dikemes.edu.gr HOURS AVAILABLE: 12:40

More information

The Nature of Intention

The Nature of Intention The Nature of Intention Gil Alexander Percival University College London Department of Philosophy PhD! 1! Declaration I, Gil Alexander Percival, confirm that the work presented in this thesis is my own.

More information

Utilitarianism: For and Against (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1973), pp Reprinted in Moral Luck (CUP, 1981).

Utilitarianism: For and Against (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1973), pp Reprinted in Moral Luck (CUP, 1981). Draft of 3-21- 13 PHIL 202: Core Ethics; Winter 2013 Core Sequence in the History of Ethics, 2011-2013 IV: 19 th and 20 th Century Moral Philosophy David O. Brink Handout #14: Williams, Internalism, and

More information

Choosing Rationally and Choosing Correctly *

Choosing Rationally and Choosing Correctly * Choosing Rationally and Choosing Correctly * Ralph Wedgwood 1 Two views of practical reason Suppose that you are faced with several different options (that is, several ways in which you might act in a

More information

On the Origins and Normative Status of the Impartial Spectator

On the Origins and Normative Status of the Impartial Spectator Discuss this article at Journaltalk: http://journaltalk.net/articles/5916 ECON JOURNAL WATCH 13(2) May 2016: 306 311 On the Origins and Normative Status of the Impartial Spectator John McHugh 1 LINK TO

More information

Is there a good epistemological argument against platonism? DAVID LIGGINS

Is there a good epistemological argument against platonism? DAVID LIGGINS [This is the penultimate draft of an article that appeared in Analysis 66.2 (April 2006), 135-41, available here by permission of Analysis, the Analysis Trust, and Blackwell Publishing. The definitive

More information

BonJour Against Materialism. Just an intellectual bandwagon?

BonJour Against Materialism. Just an intellectual bandwagon? BonJour Against Materialism Just an intellectual bandwagon? What is physicalism/materialism? materialist (or physicalist) views: views that hold that mental states are entirely material or physical in

More information

International Phenomenological Society

International Phenomenological Society International Phenomenological Society John Searle's The Construction of Social Reality Author(s): David-Hillel Ruben Reviewed work(s): Source: Philosophy and Phenomenological Research, Vol. 57, No. 2

More information

HOW TO BE (AND HOW NOT TO BE) A NORMATIVE REALIST:

HOW TO BE (AND HOW NOT TO BE) A NORMATIVE REALIST: 1 HOW TO BE (AND HOW NOT TO BE) A NORMATIVE REALIST: A DISSERTATION OVERVIEW THAT ASSUMES AS LITTLE AS POSSIBLE ABOUT MY READER S PHILOSOPHICAL BACKGROUND Consider the question, What am I going to have

More information

How Problematic for Morality Is Internalism about Reasons? Simon Robertson

How Problematic for Morality Is Internalism about Reasons? Simon Robertson Philosophy Science Scientific Philosophy Proceedings of GAP.5, Bielefeld 22. 26.09.2003 1. How Problematic for Morality Is Internalism about Reasons? Simon Robertson One of the unifying themes of Bernard

More information

UTILITARIANISM AND INFINITE UTILITY. Peter Vallentyne. Australasian Journal of Philosophy 71 (1993): I. Introduction

UTILITARIANISM AND INFINITE UTILITY. Peter Vallentyne. Australasian Journal of Philosophy 71 (1993): I. Introduction UTILITARIANISM AND INFINITE UTILITY Peter Vallentyne Australasian Journal of Philosophy 71 (1993): 212-7. I. Introduction Traditional act utilitarianism judges an action permissible just in case it produces

More information

1/13. Locke on Power

1/13. Locke on Power 1/13 Locke on Power Locke s chapter on power is the longest chapter of the Essay Concerning Human Understanding and its claims are amongst the most controversial and influential that Locke sets out in

More information

William Hasker s discussion of the Thomistic doctrine of the soul

William Hasker s discussion of the Thomistic doctrine of the soul Response to William Hasker s The Dialectic of Soul and Body John Haldane I. William Hasker s discussion of the Thomistic doctrine of the soul does not engage directly with Aquinas s writings but draws

More information

Adam Smith and the Limits of Empiricism

Adam Smith and the Limits of Empiricism Adam Smith and the Limits of Empiricism In the debate between rationalism and sentimentalism, one of the strongest weapons in the rationalist arsenal is the notion that some of our actions ought to be

More information

CONVENTIONALISM AND NORMATIVITY

CONVENTIONALISM AND NORMATIVITY 1 CONVENTIONALISM AND NORMATIVITY TORBEN SPAAK We have seen (in Section 3) that Hart objects to Austin s command theory of law, that it cannot account for the normativity of law, and that what is missing

More information

Could have done otherwise, action sentences and anaphora

Could have done otherwise, action sentences and anaphora Could have done otherwise, action sentences and anaphora HELEN STEWARD What does it mean to say of a certain agent, S, that he or she could have done otherwise? Clearly, it means nothing at all, unless

More information

PARFIT'S MISTAKEN METAETHICS Michael Smith

PARFIT'S MISTAKEN METAETHICS Michael Smith PARFIT'S MISTAKEN METAETHICS Michael Smith In the first volume of On What Matters, Derek Parfit defends a distinctive metaethical view, a view that specifies the relationships he sees between reasons,

More information

NORMATIVITY WITHOUT NORMATIVISM 1

NORMATIVITY WITHOUT NORMATIVISM 1 FORO DE DEBATE / DEBATE FORUM 195 NORMATIVITY WITHOUT NORMATIVISM 1 Jesús Zamora-Bonilla jpzb@fsof.uned.es UNED, Madrid. Spain. Stephen Turner s book Explaining the Normative (Polity, Oxford, 2010) constitutes

More information

Comments on Seumas Miller s review of Social Ontology: Collective Intentionality and Group agents in the Notre Dame Philosophical Reviews (April 20, 2

Comments on Seumas Miller s review of Social Ontology: Collective Intentionality and Group agents in the Notre Dame Philosophical Reviews (April 20, 2 Comments on Seumas Miller s review of Social Ontology: Collective Intentionality and Group agents in the Notre Dame Philosophical Reviews (April 20, 2014) Miller s review contains many misunderstandings

More information

Free Will, Agent Causation, and Disappearing Agents. Randolph Clarke

Free Will, Agent Causation, and Disappearing Agents. Randolph Clarke Free Will, Agent Causation, and Disappearing Agents Randolph Clarke Accepted Manuscript, Noûs Until quite recently, few philosophers endorsed the view that there is causation by substances that is ontologically

More information

5 A Modal Version of the

5 A Modal Version of the 5 A Modal Version of the Ontological Argument E. J. L O W E Moreland, J. P.; Sweis, Khaldoun A.; Meister, Chad V., Jul 01, 2013, Debating Christian Theism The original version of the ontological argument

More information

book-length treatments of the subject have been scarce. 1 of Zimmerman s book quite welcome. Zimmerman takes up several of the themes Moore

book-length treatments of the subject have been scarce. 1 of Zimmerman s book quite welcome. Zimmerman takes up several of the themes Moore Michael Zimmerman s The Nature of Intrinsic Value Ben Bradley The concept of intrinsic value is central to ethical theory, yet in recent years highquality book-length treatments of the subject have been

More information

Wittgenstein and Moore s Paradox

Wittgenstein and Moore s Paradox Wittgenstein and Moore s Paradox Marie McGinn, Norwich Introduction In Part II, Section x, of the Philosophical Investigations (PI ), Wittgenstein discusses what is known as Moore s Paradox. Wittgenstein

More information

Resemblance Nominalism and counterparts

Resemblance Nominalism and counterparts ANAL63-3 4/15/2003 2:40 PM Page 221 Resemblance Nominalism and counterparts Alexander Bird 1. Introduction In his (2002) Gonzalo Rodriguez-Pereyra provides a powerful articulation of the claim that Resemblance

More information

The Internal and External Components of Cognition. Ralph Wedgwood

The Internal and External Components of Cognition. Ralph Wedgwood The Internal and External Components of Cognition Ralph Wedgwood In his chapter in this volume, Timothy Williamson presents several arguments that seek to cast doubt on the idea that cognition can be factorized

More information

The fact that some action, A, is part of a valuable and eligible pattern of action, P, is a reason to perform A. 1

The fact that some action, A, is part of a valuable and eligible pattern of action, P, is a reason to perform A. 1 The Common Structure of Kantianism and Act Consequentialism Christopher Woodard RoME 2009 1. My thesis is that Kantian ethics and Act Consequentialism share a common structure, since both can be well understood

More information

Wittgenstein on the Fallacy of the Argument from Pretence. Abstract

Wittgenstein on the Fallacy of the Argument from Pretence. Abstract Wittgenstein on the Fallacy of the Argument from Pretence Edoardo Zamuner Abstract This paper is concerned with the answer Wittgenstein gives to a specific version of the sceptical problem of other minds.

More information

THE POSSIBILITY OF AN ALL-KNOWING GOD

THE POSSIBILITY OF AN ALL-KNOWING GOD THE POSSIBILITY OF AN ALL-KNOWING GOD The Possibility of an All-Knowing God Jonathan L. Kvanvig Assistant Professor of Philosophy Texas A & M University Palgrave Macmillan Jonathan L. Kvanvig, 1986 Softcover

More information

AN INTRODUCTION TO THE PHILOSOPHY OF MIND

AN INTRODUCTION TO THE PHILOSOPHY OF MIND AN INTRODUCTION TO THE PHILOSOPHY OF MIND E. J. LOWE University of Durham PUBLISHED BY THE PRESS SYNDICATE OF THE UNIVERSITY OF CAMBRIDGE The Pitt Building, Trumpington Street, Cambridge, United Kingdom

More information

Reviewed by Colin Marshall, University of Washington

Reviewed by Colin Marshall, University of Washington Yitzhak Y. Melamed, Spinoza s Metaphysics: Substance and Thought, Oxford: Oxford University Press, 2013, xxii + 232 p. Reviewed by Colin Marshall, University of Washington I n his important new study of

More information

Tuukka Kaidesoja Précis of Naturalizing Critical Realist Social Ontology

Tuukka Kaidesoja Précis of Naturalizing Critical Realist Social Ontology Journal of Social Ontology 2015; 1(2): 321 326 Book Symposium Open Access Tuukka Kaidesoja Précis of Naturalizing Critical Realist Social Ontology DOI 10.1515/jso-2015-0016 Abstract: This paper introduces

More information

Raimo Tuomela: Social Ontology: Collective Intentionality and Group Agents. New York, USA: Oxford University Press, 2013, 326 pp.

Raimo Tuomela: Social Ontology: Collective Intentionality and Group Agents. New York, USA: Oxford University Press, 2013, 326 pp. Journal of Social Ontology 2015; 1(1): 183 187 Book Review Open Access DOI 10.1515/jso-2014-0040 Raimo Tuomela: Social Ontology: Collective Intentionality and Group Agents. New York, USA: Oxford University

More information

Many Minds are No Worse than One

Many Minds are No Worse than One Replies 233 Many Minds are No Worse than One David Papineau 1 Introduction 2 Consciousness 3 Probability 1 Introduction The Everett-style interpretation of quantum mechanics developed by Michael Lockwood

More information