Reply to Kirk and Melnyk

Size: px
Start display at page:

Download "Reply to Kirk and Melnyk"

Transcription

1 SWIF Philosophy of Mind, 09 May Forums Forum 4 Reply to Kirk and Melnyk David Papineau Department of Philosophy King's College London I am lucky to have two such penetrating commentators as Robert Kirk and Andrew Melnyk. It is also fortunate that they come at me from different directions, and so cover different aspects of my book. Robert Kirk has doubts about the overall structure of my enterprise, and in particular about my central commitment to a distinctive species of phenomenal concepts. Andrew Melnyk, by contrast, offers no objections to my general brand of materialism. Instead he focuses specifically on my discussion of the anti-materialist 'intuition of distinctness', raising questions about my attempt to explain this intuition away, and offering alternative suggestions of his own. Let me first discuss Robert Kirk's comments. This will enable me to clarify some of the central themes of the book. After that, I shall turn to Andrew Melnyk's helpful comments on the intuition of distinctness. Kirk's Comments Kirk is unhappy with the 'inflationist materialism' that underpins the overall argument of my book. An 'inflationist' thinks that there are special ways of thinking about conscious states using phenomenal concepts which are a priori distinct from all other ways of thinking about conscious states, and in particular from functionalist ways of thinking about conscious states. Because of this, inflationist materialists will deny that materialism requires all true claims to follow a priori from the physical truths (that is, they will reject the 'a priori characterization of materialism'). Of course, inflationist materialists will allow that some kinds of non-physical claims follow a priori from the physical truths. Insofar as we refer to water using an everyday concept that invokes the causal role of water, then we can arguably deduce all true claims about water from a complete inventory of physical truths, for these truths will tell us that H 2 O is the physical stuff that plays the watery role. But if phenomenal concepts don't invoke any causal roles, then there will be no such analogous a priori deduction of phenomenal claims from physical truths. ('Inflationist materialism' is another name for David Chalmers' 'Type-B materialism' (Chalmers, 2002). I would say that this position is now the standard view among materialist philosophers of mind. (Cf. Horgan, 1984, Peacocke, 1989, Loar 1990, Papineau, 1993, Sturgeon, 1994, Hill, 1997, Hill and McLaughlin, 1998, Tye, 1999.)) In the last section of his comments Kirk defends the 'a priori characterization of materialism' against inflationist materialism. As a materialist, he then has to deny any a priori divide between our concepts of conscious states and our grasp of their functional roles. I shall say something about Kirk's views about our concepts of conscious states in a moment. But first I would like to point out that the 'a priori characterization of materialism' makes extremely strong demands in general, even outside the realm of the mind-brain relation.

2 Take claims made using proper names Tully had brown hair, say. Let us suppose that the totality of physical truths does indeed tell us about the hair colour of all the humans who ever existed. Still, will it tell us which of those human beings is Tully? In order for this to be deducible a priori from the physical truths, our grasp of the name 'Tully' will have to carry with it enough a priori information for us to single out Tully from all other humans. I see no reason to suppose that our competence with the name 'Tully' ensures this. After all, it is a commonplace of modern philosophy of language that our ability to use 'Tully' referentially depends inter alia on our causal-historical links to Tully, rather than on any uniquely identifying a priori description. (And the same goes for many other referring terms, apart from proper names of people.) I take this point to discredit the a priori characterization of materialism. It is clearly no argument against materialism that Tully had brown hair cannot be deduced a priori from physical truths. The barrier is not that Tully had brown hair commits us to something non-physical. It is just that we can understand 'Tully' without knowing how to pick out Tully from all the purely physically specified people. Similarly, I say, with phenomenal terms. We cannot deduce that phenomenal pain is nociceptive-specific neuronal activity, say, a priori from the physical truths. But this isn't because 'phenomenal pain' refers to something non-physical. It's just that we can have the concept of phenomenal pain without knowing how to pick out its referent from among all the purely physically specified states. This is why I think zombie worlds are conceivable but not possible. Since there is no a priori route from the physical truths to phenomenal pain, we will not violate any conceptual constraints if we posit a being that shares all our physical properties but not our phenomenal pains. Yet, for all that, if phenomenal pains are material states, then such a being will not be possible, by the necessity of identity. [1] Let me now turn to Kirk's suggestions about our concepts of conscious states. Since Kirk is a materialist who upholds the a priori characterization of materialism, he must maintain that these concepts will allow us to deduce the phenomenal facts a priori from the physical facts. Given this, he faces a prima facie difficulty with Frank Jackson's famous 'Mary' thought-experiment, since at first sight the post-exposure Mary would seem to acquire phenomenal concepts that can't be linked a priori with the physical facts. So somehow Kirk must resist taking the Mary story at face value. (Here Kirk is in the same boat as the contemporary Frank Jackson. Since formulating the 'knowledge argument', Jackson has become persuaded that materialism must be true (Jackson, forthcoming). However, his original knowledge argument successfully demonstrates that materialism is inconsistent with the two claims (a) that Mary shows that our phenomenal concepts are a priori detached from the physical facts, and (b) that materialism requires phenomenal claims to follow a priori from the physical truths. So Jackson has been forced to give up (a) or (b). Somewhat surprisingly, he has stuck to (b), and given up (a). That is, he has kept faith with the a priori characterization of materialism, but now denies that the Mary story shows that phenomenal concepts are a priori detached the physical facts. If you ask me, he has kept the bad bit of the knowledge argument, and thrown away the good bit. The Mary story is a terrific demonstration of distinct phenomenal concepts. By contrast, the a priori characterization of materialism strikes me as quite misguided.) It is not entirely clear from Kirk's comments how he himself would deal with the Mary thought-experiment. He is happy to allow that there is a sense in which Mary acquires new phenomenal concepts of her new experiences when she comes out of her grey prison. But he denies that these new concepts are entirely distinct

3 from the old functional concepts that she could previously have used to refer to those experiences. Even if phenomenal concepts 'are not be linked in any obvious or direct way with... functional concepts, they may still be linked in indirect, unobvious ways'. Again, Kirk allows that we may 'have two very different ways of using our concept of pain... But that does not seem enough to justify the claim that there are two concepts.' However, I do not see how these claims can be reconciled with a variant of the Mary thought-experiment that I discuss in my book. This is the case where Mary is shown a coloured piece of paper when she emerges from her grey prison, but isn't told what colour it is. Now she has a new concept ('that kind of experience'), but this concept surely has no links, however indirect and unobvious, with any functional concepts. Mary can think about the type of experience in question, but no amount of a priori reflection is going to enable her to figure out its characteristic causes or effects. By the same coin, she will surely have no way of inferring the satisfaction of her new phenomenal concept a priori from the totality of physical truths. Let me respond to one final aspect of Kirk's comments. He feels that, if phenomenal-material identities were brute not deducible a priori from the physical facts then they would be mysterious. In the book, I claim that brute phenomenal-material identities are no more mysterious than brute proper names identities like Cicero = Tully. Kirk objects that 'the conditions for giving a man a name are easily understood and easily satisfied, while that is not so for the case of applying phenomenal concepts to physical properties'. Now, I concede phenomenal concepts may not be so 'easily understood' as proper names. But Thinking about Consciousness is a sustained attempt to remedy this, by elaborating a detailed account of how phenomenal concepts work, and in particular of how they can have physical referents, even though they are not associated a priori with any functional roles. This account is no doubt flawed in particular respects, but I see no reason in principle to rule out some such explanation of how phenomenal concepts apply to physical properties. Melnyk's Comments In the book I do agree that there is something intuitively mysterious about mindbrain identities. But I deny that this feeling of mystery derives from the non-role nature of phenomenal concepts and our consequent inability to deduce the phenomenal facts a priori from the physical facts. Many contemporary philosophers refer to the absence of such a priori brain-mind deductions as 'the explanatory gap' (Levine, 1983). As an inflationist materialist, I of course accept that there is such an 'explanatory gap' there are indeed no a priori brain-mind deductions. However I don't think that this 'explanatory gap' is why we find the relationship of mind to brain so puzzling. 'Explanatory gaps' of this kind are twoa-penny, arising with the many other referring terms, such as ordinary proper names, which don't pick out their referents via roles. The feeling of mystery we feel in the mind-brain case is something else again it is a real 'intuitive gap' rather than the commonplace and unpuzzling 'explanatory gap'. To understand the source of this intuitive gap we need to look elsewhere. Andrew Melnyk's comments focus on my analysis of this intuitive gap. He starts by noting that my central claim about a widespread 'intuition of (mind-brain) distinctness' is allied with the stronger thesis that this intuition of distinctness isn't just a nagging doubt, but actually stops any of us 'really believing' materialism. Moreover, as he notes, I do little to defend, or indeed clarify, this stronger claim in the book. Let me try to do a bit better here.

4 To get a hold on the issue, let me explain why I want to claim that none of us including dyed-in-the-wool materialists like myself really believes materialism. I need this claim in order to explain why even paid-up materialists continue to react to mind-brain identities in ways which according to my analysis commit them to dualism. To be specific, I need the claim to explain why even paid-up materialists continue to feel that zombies are prima facie possible; and I need it to explain why paid-up materialists continue to share the widespread feeling that there is something mysterious about mind-brain identities. In the book I argue in detail that neither of these reactions is explicable by the commonplace 'explanatory gap' that is, by reference to the a priori separation of phenomenal concepts from functional and other material concepts. For we have the same a priori separation in other cases, such as proper name identities, yet people who come to accept such identities don't continue to regard them as mysterious, or their falsity as apparently possible (rather, they come to think: Cicero couldn't fail to be Tully after all, they're the same person). So I offer an alternative explanation for these persistent reactions in the mind-brain case: we have these persistent reactions because we don't really believe that phenomenal states are brain states to start with and then, of course, we do find their relation mysterious ('Why ever should brain states be accompanied by phenomenal states?'), and do think that brain states without phenomenal states are possible (simply because we think they are distinct properties, even if correlated in the actual world). This now puts the question of disbelieving mind-brain identities into better focus. I need to attribute such disbelief to people to just the extent that they manifest the dualist reactions to mind-brain identities. In the book I simply assumed that even professed materialists will continue to have these dualist reactions, and inferred from this that they must really disbelieve materialism, despite any avowals to the contrary. But, now Andrew Melnyk has raised the issue, I see that there is room for a more nuanced treatment. Perhaps different professed materialists continue to have the dualist reactions to different degrees. While some might continue to feel them fully, others might only feel them to a lesser degree ('Zombies don't strike me as so obviously possible any more'), and yet others might lose the reactions almost entirely. Correspondingly, alongside those professed materialists who don't actually believe materialism, there may also be those who give materialism some nontrivial degree of belief, and also those who give materialism pretty much full credence (for whom dualism is indeed just a 'nagging doubt'). Again, there could be complexities in the mode in which dualism is believed, rather than the degree. It is not always straightforward whether someone believes some proposition. You can fully believe something at a theoretical level, yet disbelieve it at some more primitive level. Consider people who cross their fingers when the aeroplane is taking off, or people who are 'in denial' about something for which they have overwhelming evidence, or indeed people who undergo the Müller-Lyer illusion. In all these cases, there is a sense in which they both believe and disbelieve something. Maybe this is how it is with many professed materialists. They believe materialism at a theoretical level, but at some more primitive level they remain in the grip of dualism. Their primitive disbelief will then offer an explanation of their continued dualist reactions. To the extent that their thinking is influenced by their primitive disbelief in materialism, zombies will continue to strike them as possible, and the mind-brain relation will continue to seem mysterious. Let me now turn from the issue of how far all of us believe dualism to the question of why we do so. In the book I offer 'the antipathetic fallacy' as my explanation. Melnyk raises some doubts about this explanation, and offers some

5 alternative suggestions of his own. But before considering his points, it will help to make a methodological observation. When I first aired my 'antipathetic' diagnosis to colleagues in London in the early 1990s, my friend Scott Sturgeon said 'That's an interesting sociological hypothesis'. I was somewhat taken aback at this apparently belittling reaction to some years of hard philosophical work, but I quickly realized Scott was quite right. Claims about the source of dualist thoughts are clearly empirical claims, answering to facts about the cognitive processes of the individuals covered by the claims. This means that we need not regard such claims as a yes-or-no matter. One explanation for dualist thoughts may apply to some individuals, another to different individuals. I shall not dwell on this point in what follows, but readers will do well to bear it in mind. (This fits with the point made a moment ago, that the whether everybody believes dualism isn't a yes-or-no matter either, even before we start asking why. Just as different people may believe dualism to different degrees, and in different modes, so also may they believe if for different reasons.) Melnyk wonders whether my 'antipathetic fallacy' is the right explanation for our intuitive inclinations towards dualism (the 'intuition of distinctness' henceforth). On my hypothesis, the fact that material concepts do not use phenomenal properties confuses people into thinking that material concepts do not mention them either. Of course, most referring concepts don't use the items they mention, but my idea, as Melnyk explains, is that it is specifically the comparison with phenomenal concepts, which do use the phenomenal states they refer to, that confuses people here. Melnyk observes that my story requires some pretty sophisticated mental capacities. I need to suppose that, when people refer to some phenomenal state with some phenomenal concept, they can simultaneously think about their deployment of that phenomenal concept, and note that it involves that same phenomenal state. I agree that this is a pretty sophisticated ability, but not necessarily one that is beyond ordinary people (as Melnyk himself allows). Think what happens when people are invited to reflect on whether 'This technicolour phenomenology be produced by soggy grey matter'. They introspect or imagine seeing colours on the left hand side, and then note that the phenomenology of these acts is absent when they think of soggy grey matter on the right hand side. Moreover, it is worth remembering that my story doesn't require ordinary people to keep a very clear grip on what is going on in such cases on the contrary, I suppose that, once they have vaguely noted that material concepts 'leave out' the feelings associated with phenomenal concepts, they then proceed to get caught up in a fallacious use-mention muddle. Melnyk has a more definite worry about the antipathetic fallacy. Suppose ordinary people do note that their deployment of phenomenal concepts involves being in the phenomenal state referred to. Why ever should they conclude on this basis, via some sort of one-shot induction, that all concepts that refer to phenomenal states must so involve being in those states? Well, I agree that it is implausible that ordinary people should make such an induction. But that is not my hypothesis. To grasp clearly that phenomenal concepts use the selfsame phenomenal states that they mention, and to infer from this that all concepts that refer to phenomenal states must do the same, would be a rash induction, but at least it would be cogent. The reasoning I attribute to ordinary people is not rash, but muddled. They somehow note that non-phenomenal concepts 'leave out' the phenomenal states that phenomenal concepts 'involve', and fallaciously infer from this that non-phenomenal concepts don't refer to phenomenal states. If they could see clearly that the 'involvement' of phenomenal states in phenomenal concepts is a matter of the concepts simultaneously both using and mentioning the states, as Melnyk's inductive reconstruction of the antipathetic fallacy has it,

6 then they would already be articulating things in a way that would enable them to avoid the confusion I attribute to them. Perhaps Melnyk would want to pursue this line of objection. Let us agree that the antipathetic fallacy involves a kind of use-mention confusion, rather than a rash induction. Still, why should this confusion arise only with concepts that refer to phenomenal states, and not with other kinds of concepts? But here there is a ready answer. We can think phenomenally about the deployment of any concept. But only in the case of phenomenal concepts will this phenomenal introspection inevitably mean we are also thinking about something phenomenally similar to the referent of the concept. For only phenomenal concepts refer by simultaneously activating some phenomenal state that is like their referent. So phenomenal concepts are indeed peculiar, in introspectively appearing to 'involve' their referents in a way that makes other ways of referring to those referents seem pale by comparison. I want now to take up Melnyk's alternative positive suggestion about the source of the intuition of distinctness. This is that phenomenal and material concepts may be so cognitively differently that it is impossible for us to 'merge files' in the way we generally do when embracing an identity claim. In the book I briefly consider this suggestion, only to dismiss it on the grounds that phenomenal concepts are closely related to perceptual concepts, yet no such cognitive barrier seems to block file-merging across the perceptual-theoretical divide. Melnyk raises two doubts about this line of argument. First, he suggests I may be wrong to hold that there is no cognitive barrier to file-merging across the perceptualtheoretical divide. Second, and independently, he suggests that differences between the phenomenal and perceptual cases might explain why perceptualtheoretical file-merging is possible even when phenomenal-material file-merging is not. I am more persuaded by the first suggestion than the second. Let me consider them in reverse order. Melnyk second suggestion is that there may be a barrier to file-merging in the phenomenal-material case that is absent in the perceptual-theoretical case. His suggestion relates specifically to phenomenal concepts that are only usable when you are actually having the states they refer to ('That is going on in me now') and which don't even involve the ability to re-identify those states as the same again. In such cases, Melnyk suggests, any temporary file associated with the phenomenal concept would simply be too transient to be merged with any permanent material concept file. I find this unpersuasive for three reasons. First, I find it doubtful that any genuine referring term should be so transient as to be unavailable for merging with others; what's the point of being able to acquire facts involving some entity if you can't slot them informatively into your overall picture of the world? Second, I doubt that any phenomenal concepts fit Melnyk's very simple model; to pick out some phenomenal states as 'that ' requires at least that you be able to attend to it, and it seems empirically likely that you can reidentify any experiences you can attend to. Third, I don't see why the kind of construction Melnyk has in mind should yield an asymmetry between phenomenal and perceptual concepts; any demonstrative analysis of phenomenal concepts would seem to have a natural parallel for perceptual concepts (thus, along with 'that (experience)', we would have 'that (observable property)'). Melnyk's first suggestion does not try to drive a wedge between the phenomenalmaterial and perceptual-theoretical cases; rather, he goes along with my assumption that the two cases stand or fall together, but argues that perceptualtheoretical examples support the conclusion that file-merging is blocked in both cases. In the book I argued the other way, urging that file-merging is possible in both cases: thus I maintained that there is no barrier to merging a visual concept of a kestrel (such as might be derived from first-hand observation) with a

7 theoretical concept of a kestrel (as might be derived from a textbook of evolutionary biology). Melnyk wonders whether the impression that such merging is possible might not derive from our tendency to slice off the secondary qualities from the visually-conceived kestrels, so to speak, thus making it easier to conflate them with the theoretically-conceived kestrels. But if this is what is going on, he points out, it provides no argument for the possibility of phenomenalmaterial mergers. For we have made the perceptual-theoretical merger possible only by moving the hard parts the secondary qualities into the mind; so mergers which do involve these hard parts may well still be cognitively unviable. As I said, I find this line of argument relatively persuasive. There is a lot more to say about it, and in particular about the relationship between phenomenal and perceptual concepts. But rather than pursue this complex issue here, let me finish on an irenic note, by recalling the methodological point made earlier. Explanations of the intuition of distinctness need not be a yes-or-no matter. We do not need to choose between the antipathetic fallacy and the no-file-merging explanations. Perhaps one explanation works in some cases, and the other works in other cases. Or perhaps the two explanations sometimes complement each other: there may be people who wouldn't succumb to the antipathetic fallacy on its own, and who wouldn't be stopped from merging files solely by the cognitive divergence of phenomenal and material concepts, but who capitulate to the two influences acting in concert. References Chalmers, D The Conscious Mind. Oxford: Oxford University Press. Chalmers, D 'Consciousness and its Place in Nature', in Stich, S. and Warfield, F. (eds) The Blackwell Guide to Philosophy of Mind. Oxford: Blackwell. Hill, C 'Imaginability, Conceivability, Possibility, and the Mind-Body Problem.' Philosophical Studies, 87. Hill, C. and McLaughlin, B 'There are Fewer Things in Reality that are Dreamt of in Chalmers' Philosophy.' Philosophy and Phenomenonological Research, 59. Horgan, T 'Jackson on Physical Information and Qualia.' Philosophical Quarterly, 32. Jackson, F. Forthcoming. 'Mind and Illusion.' Levine, J 'Materialism and Qualia: The Explanatory Gap.' Pacific Philosophical Quarterly, 64. Loar, B 'Phenomenal States', in Tomberlin, J. (ed.) Philosophical Perspectives, 4. Papineau, D Philosophical Naturalism. Oxford: Blackwell. Peacocke, C 'No Resting Place: A Critical Notice of The View from Nowhere.' Philosophical Review, 98. Sturgeon, S 'The Epistemic View of Subjectivity.' Journal of Philosophy, 91 Tye, M 'Phenomenal Consciousness: The Explanatory Gap.' Mind, 108. Notes

8 [Note 1] Kirk wonders how I would respond to David Chalmers' appeal to 'twodimensional semantics' to cast doubt on such materialist a posteriori necessary identities (Chalmers, 1996). I don't discuss 'two-dimensional semantics' explicitly in the book, but I think a clear enough answer is implicit there. Chalmers supposes that all terms have a 'primary intension', in addition to their referents as normally conceived. This 'primary intension' consists of those entities that the term would pick out in other possible worlds 'considered as actual' (for example, 'water' would pick out XYZ if the actual world's watery stuff were XYZ rather than H 2 O). Chalmers then assumes that, if the claim that a b is so much as conceivable (for example, water H 2 O ), this must be because 'a ''s and 'b ''s 'primary intensions diverge' (there must be worlds in which the terms 'water' and 'H 2 O' would pick out different items), from which it follows that there is a genuinely possible world corresponding to the thought a b. Applying this to the mind-brain case, we then get the Kripkean thesis that, if it is so much as conceivable that pain M, where 'M' is some material concept, then there must be genuine possibilities where 'pain' and 'M' pick out different items. Moreover, if 'pain' is a priori distinct from all material concepts, as the inflationist materialist assumes, then this must mean that 'pain' must refer by invoking some distinctively non-material entity. As an inflationist materialist, I respond to all this simply by denying Chalmers' crucial premise. I don't accept that, whenever some a b is conceivable, then 'a ' and 'b ' must have 'primary intensions' which diverge. The terms 'a ' and 'b ' may simply refer directly, which means they won't have any 'primary intensions' different from their normal referents (different from their 'secondary intensions'). We can still conceive a b without conceptual contradiction, simply because 'a ' and 'b ' are different terms which are not interchangeable in our cognitive economy. But it does not follow from this that 'a ' and 'b ' must have different 'primary intensions', that they must pick out their referents in ways that would give them different referents in other possible worlds 'considered as actual'.

THE TWO-DIMENSIONAL ARGUMENT AGAINST MATERIALISM AND ITS SEMANTIC PREMISE

THE TWO-DIMENSIONAL ARGUMENT AGAINST MATERIALISM AND ITS SEMANTIC PREMISE Diametros nr 29 (wrzesień 2011): 80-92 THE TWO-DIMENSIONAL ARGUMENT AGAINST MATERIALISM AND ITS SEMANTIC PREMISE Karol Polcyn 1. PRELIMINARIES Chalmers articulates his argument in terms of two-dimensional

More information

Experiences Don t Sum

Experiences Don t Sum Philip Goff Experiences Don t Sum According to Galen Strawson, there could be no such thing as brute emergence. If weallow thatcertain x s can emergefromcertain y s in a way that is unintelligible, even

More information

Explanatory gaps and dualist intuitions

Explanatory gaps and dualist intuitions 02-Weiskrantz-Chap02 4/3/08 5:32 PM Page 55 Chapter 2 Explanatory gaps and dualist intuitions David Papineau 2.1 Introduction I agree with nearly everything Martin Davies says. He has written an elegant

More information

DECONSTRUCTING NEW WAVE MATERIALISM

DECONSTRUCTING NEW WAVE MATERIALISM In C. Gillett & B. Loewer, eds., Physicalism and Its Discontents (Cambridge University Press, 2001) DECONSTRUCTING NEW WAVE MATERIALISM Terence Horgan and John Tienson University of Memphis. In the first

More information

There are two explanatory gaps. Dr Tom McClelland University of Glasgow

There are two explanatory gaps. Dr Tom McClelland University of Glasgow There are two explanatory gaps Dr Tom McClelland University of Glasgow 1 THERE ARE TWO EXPLANATORY GAPS ABSTRACT The explanatory gap between the physical and the phenomenal is at the heart of the Problem

More information

Thinking About Consciousness

Thinking About Consciousness 774 Book Reviews rates most efficiently from each other the complexity of what there is in Jean- Jacques Rousseau s text, and the process by which the reader has encountered it. In a most original and

More information

Review of Torin Alter and Sven Walter (eds.) Phenomenal Concepts and Phenomenal Knowledge: New Essays on Consciousness and Physicalism

Review of Torin Alter and Sven Walter (eds.) Phenomenal Concepts and Phenomenal Knowledge: New Essays on Consciousness and Physicalism Review of Torin Alter and Sven Walter (eds.) Phenomenal Concepts and Phenomenal Knowledge: New Essays on Consciousness and Physicalism James Trafford University of East London jamestrafford1@googlemail.com

More information

Purple Haze: The Puzzle of Consciousness

Purple Haze: The Puzzle of Consciousness Purple Haze: The Puzzle of Consciousness The MIT Faculty has made this article openly available. Please share how this access benefits you. Your story matters. Citation As Published Publisher Levine, Joseph.

More information

Varieties of Apriority

Varieties of Apriority S E V E N T H E X C U R S U S Varieties of Apriority T he notions of a priori knowledge and justification play a central role in this work. There are many ways in which one can understand the a priori,

More information

Physicalism and Conceptual Analysis * Esa Díaz-León.

Physicalism and Conceptual Analysis * Esa Díaz-León. Physicalism and Conceptual Analysis * Esa Díaz-León pip01ed@sheffield.ac.uk Physicalism is a widely held claim about the nature of the world. But, as it happens, it also has its detractors. The first step

More information

On David Chalmers's The Conscious Mind

On David Chalmers's The Conscious Mind Philosophy and Phenomenological Research Vol. LIX, No.2, June 1999 On David Chalmers's The Conscious Mind SYDNEY SHOEMAKER Cornell University One does not have to agree with the main conclusions of David

More information

IN THIS PAPER I will examine and criticize the arguments David

IN THIS PAPER I will examine and criticize the arguments David A MATERIALIST RESPONSE TO DAVID CHALMERS THE CONSCIOUS MIND PAUL RAYMORE Stanford University IN THIS PAPER I will examine and criticize the arguments David Chalmers gives for rejecting a materialistic

More information

Mind the Gap. David Papineau - King's College London. 1. Introduction

Mind the Gap. David Papineau - King's College London. 1. Introduction Mind the Gap David Papineau - King's College London 1. Introduction On the first page of The Problem of Consciousness (1991), Colin McGinn asks "How is it possible for conscious states to depend on brain

More information

Chalmers, "Consciousness and Its Place in Nature"

Chalmers, Consciousness and Its Place in Nature http://www.protevi.com/john/philmind Classroom use only. Chalmers, "Consciousness and Its Place in Nature" 1. Intro 2. The easy problem and the hard problem 3. The typology a. Reductive Materialism i.

More information

Primitive Concepts. David J. Chalmers

Primitive Concepts. David J. Chalmers Primitive Concepts David J. Chalmers Conceptual Analysis: A Traditional View A traditional view: Most ordinary concepts (or expressions) can be defined in terms of other more basic concepts (or expressions)

More information

The Phenomenal Concept Strategy

The Phenomenal Concept Strategy Peter Carruthers and Bénédicte Veillet 1 The Phenomenal Concept Strategy A powerful reply to a range of familiar anti-physicalist arguments has recently been developed. According to this reply, our possession

More information

Revelation and physicalism

Revelation and physicalism Synthese (2017) 194:2345 2366 DOI 10.1007/s11229-016-1055-7 Revelation and physicalism Kelly Trogdon 1 Received: 11 June 2015 / Accepted: 18 February 2016 / Published online: 3 March 2016 Springer Science+Business

More information

A copy can be downloaded for personal non-commercial research or study, without prior permission or charge

A copy can be downloaded for personal non-commercial research or study, without prior permission or charge Leuenberger, S. (2012) Review of David Chalmers, The Character of Consciousness. Australasian Journal of Philosophy, 90 (4). pp. 803-806. ISSN 0004-8402 Copyright 2013 Taylor & Francis A copy can be downloaded

More information

Searle vs. Chalmers Debate, 8/2005 with Death Monkey (Kevin Dolan)

Searle vs. Chalmers Debate, 8/2005 with Death Monkey (Kevin Dolan) Searle vs. Chalmers Debate, 8/2005 with Death Monkey (Kevin Dolan) : Searle says of Chalmers book, The Conscious Mind, "it is one thing to bite the occasional bullet here and there, but this book consumes

More information

Introduction: Taking Consciousness Seriously. 1. Two Concepts of Mind I. FOUNDATIONS

Introduction: Taking Consciousness Seriously. 1. Two Concepts of Mind I. FOUNDATIONS Notes on David Chalmers The Conscious Mind (Oxford: Oxford UP, 1996) by Andrew Bailey, Philosophy Department, University of Guelph (abailey@uoguelph.ca) Introduction: Taking Consciousness Seriously...

More information

Grokking Pain. S. Yablo. draft of June 2, 2000

Grokking Pain. S. Yablo. draft of June 2, 2000 Grokking Pain S. Yablo draft of June 2, 2000 I. First a puzzle about a priori knowledge; then some morals for the philosophy of language and mind. The puzzle involves a contradiction, or seeming contradiction,

More information

Review of David J. Chalmers Constructing the World (OUP 2012) David Chalmers burst onto the philosophical scene in the mid-1990s with his work on

Review of David J. Chalmers Constructing the World (OUP 2012) David Chalmers burst onto the philosophical scene in the mid-1990s with his work on Review of David J. Chalmers Constructing the World (OUP 2012) Thomas W. Polger, University of Cincinnati 1. Introduction David Chalmers burst onto the philosophical scene in the mid-1990s with his work

More information

David Chalmers on Mind and Consciousness Richard Brown Forthcoming in Andrew Bailey (ed) Philosophy of Mind: The Key Thinkers.

David Chalmers on Mind and Consciousness Richard Brown Forthcoming in Andrew Bailey (ed) Philosophy of Mind: The Key Thinkers. David Chalmers on Mind and Consciousness Richard Brown Forthcoming in Andrew Bailey (ed) Philosophy of Mind: The Key Thinkers. Continuum Press David Chalmers is perhaps best known for his argument against

More information

DUALISM VS. MATERIALISM I

DUALISM VS. MATERIALISM I DUALISM VS. MATERIALISM I The Ontology of E. J. Lowe's Substance Dualism Alex Carruth, Philosophy, Durham Emergence Project, Durham, UNITED KINGDOM Sophie Gibb, Durham University, Durham, UNITED KINGDOM

More information

Please remember to sign-in by scanning your badge Department of Psychiatry Grand Rounds

Please remember to sign-in by scanning your badge Department of Psychiatry Grand Rounds AS A COURTESY TO OUR SPEAKER AND AUDIENCE MEMBERS, PLEASE SILENCE ALL PAGERS AND CELL PHONES Please remember to sign-in by scanning your badge Department of Psychiatry Grand Rounds James M. Stedman, PhD.

More information

Philosophy 5340 Epistemology. Topic 6: Theories of Justification: Foundationalism versus Coherentism. Part 2: Susan Haack s Foundherentist Approach

Philosophy 5340 Epistemology. Topic 6: Theories of Justification: Foundationalism versus Coherentism. Part 2: Susan Haack s Foundherentist Approach Philosophy 5340 Epistemology Topic 6: Theories of Justification: Foundationalism versus Coherentism Part 2: Susan Haack s Foundherentist Approach Susan Haack, "A Foundherentist Theory of Empirical Justification"

More information

Grounding and Analyticity. David Chalmers

Grounding and Analyticity. David Chalmers Grounding and Analyticity David Chalmers Interlevel Metaphysics Interlevel metaphysics: how the macro relates to the micro how nonfundamental levels relate to fundamental levels Grounding Triumphalism

More information

Property Dualism and the Knowledge Argument: Are Qualia Really a Problem for Physicalism? Ronald Planer Rutgers Univerity

Property Dualism and the Knowledge Argument: Are Qualia Really a Problem for Physicalism? Ronald Planer Rutgers Univerity Property Dualism and the Knowledge Argument: Are Qualia Really a Problem for Physicalism? Ronald Planer Rutgers Univerity Abstract: Where does the mind fit into the physical world? Not surprisingly, philosophers

More information

INTRODUCTION THE EPISTEMOLOGICAL ARGUMENT

INTRODUCTION THE EPISTEMOLOGICAL ARGUMENT GENERAL PHILOSOPHY WEEK 5: MIND & BODY JONNY MCINTOSH INTRODUCTION Last week: The Mind-Body Problem(s) Introduced Descartes's Argument from Doubt This week: Descartes's Epistemological Argument Frank Jackson's

More information

Moral Relativism and Conceptual Analysis. David J. Chalmers

Moral Relativism and Conceptual Analysis. David J. Chalmers Moral Relativism and Conceptual Analysis David J. Chalmers An Inconsistent Triad (1) All truths are a priori entailed by fundamental truths (2) No moral truths are a priori entailed by fundamental truths

More information

PHL340 Handout 8: Evaluating Dogmatism

PHL340 Handout 8: Evaluating Dogmatism PHL340 Handout 8: Evaluating Dogmatism 1 Dogmatism Last class we looked at Jim Pryor s paper on dogmatism about perceptual justification (for background on the notion of justification, see the handout

More information

Is phenomenal character out there in the world?

Is phenomenal character out there in the world? Is phenomenal character out there in the world? Jeff Speaks November 15, 2013 1. Standard representationalism... 2 1.1. Phenomenal properties 1.2. Experience and phenomenal character 1.3. Sensible properties

More information

BonJour Against Materialism. Just an intellectual bandwagon?

BonJour Against Materialism. Just an intellectual bandwagon? BonJour Against Materialism Just an intellectual bandwagon? What is physicalism/materialism? materialist (or physicalist) views: views that hold that mental states are entirely material or physical in

More information

Direct Realism and the Brain-in-a-Vat Argument by Michael Huemer (2000)

Direct Realism and the Brain-in-a-Vat Argument by Michael Huemer (2000) Direct Realism and the Brain-in-a-Vat Argument by Michael Huemer (2000) One of the advantages traditionally claimed for direct realist theories of perception over indirect realist theories is that the

More information

The knowledge argument purports to show that there are non-physical facts facts that cannot be expressed in

The knowledge argument purports to show that there are non-physical facts facts that cannot be expressed in The Knowledge Argument Adam Vinueza Department of Philosophy, University of Colorado vinueza@colorado.edu Keywords: acquaintance, fact, physicalism, proposition, qualia. The Knowledge Argument and Its

More information

The Qualiafications (or Lack Thereof) of Epiphenomenal Qualia

The Qualiafications (or Lack Thereof) of Epiphenomenal Qualia Francesca Hovagimian Philosophy of Psychology Professor Dinishak 5 March 2016 The Qualiafications (or Lack Thereof) of Epiphenomenal Qualia In his essay Epiphenomenal Qualia, Frank Jackson makes the case

More information

Illusionism and anti-functionalism about phenomenal consciousness. Derk Pereboom, Cornell University

Illusionism and anti-functionalism about phenomenal consciousness. Derk Pereboom, Cornell University Illusionism and anti-functionalism about phenomenal consciousness Derk Pereboom, Cornell University Journal of Consciousness Studies 23, (2016), pp. 172-85. Penultimate draft Abstract. The role of a functionalist

More information

The knowledge argument

The knowledge argument Michael Lacewing The knowledge argument PROPERTY DUALISM Property dualism is the view that, although there is just one kind of substance, physical substance, there are two fundamentally different kinds

More information

Philosophy 5340 Epistemology Topic 4: Skepticism. Part 1: The Scope of Skepticism and Two Main Types of Skeptical Argument

Philosophy 5340 Epistemology Topic 4: Skepticism. Part 1: The Scope of Skepticism and Two Main Types of Skeptical Argument 1. The Scope of Skepticism Philosophy 5340 Epistemology Topic 4: Skepticism Part 1: The Scope of Skepticism and Two Main Types of Skeptical Argument The scope of skeptical challenges can vary in a number

More information

KNOWING WHERE WE ARE, AND WHAT IT IS LIKE Robert Stalnaker

KNOWING WHERE WE ARE, AND WHAT IT IS LIKE Robert Stalnaker KNOWING WHERE WE ARE, AND WHAT IT IS LIKE Robert Stalnaker [This is work in progress - notes and references are incomplete or missing. The same may be true of some of the arguments] I am going to start

More information

Lecture 3. I argued in the previous lecture for a relationist solution to Frege's puzzle, one which

Lecture 3. I argued in the previous lecture for a relationist solution to Frege's puzzle, one which 1 Lecture 3 I argued in the previous lecture for a relationist solution to Frege's puzzle, one which posits a semantic difference between the pairs of names 'Cicero', 'Cicero' and 'Cicero', 'Tully' even

More information

Objections to the two-dimensionalism of The Conscious Mind

Objections to the two-dimensionalism of The Conscious Mind Objections to the two-dimensionalism of The Conscious Mind phil 93515 Jeff Speaks February 7, 2007 1 Problems with the rigidification of names..................... 2 1.1 Names as actually -rigidified descriptions..................

More information

Wright on response-dependence and self-knowledge

Wright on response-dependence and self-knowledge Wright on response-dependence and self-knowledge March 23, 2004 1 Response-dependent and response-independent concepts........... 1 1.1 The intuitive distinction......................... 1 1.2 Basic equations

More information

Philosophical Zombies Don t Share Our Epistemic Situation. John Curtis Wright

Philosophical Zombies Don t Share Our Epistemic Situation. John Curtis Wright Philosophical Zombies Don t Share Our Epistemic Situation John Curtis Wright Thesis submitted to the faculty of the Virginia Polytechnic Institute and State University in partial fulfillment of the requirements

More information

The Hard Problem of Consciousness & The Progressivism of Scientific Explanation

The Hard Problem of Consciousness & The Progressivism of Scientific Explanation The Hard Problem of Consciousness & The Progressivism of Scientific Explanation Several philosophers believe that with phenomenal consciousness and neural-biological properties, there will always be some

More information

Rationality in Action. By John Searle. Cambridge: MIT Press, pages, ISBN Hardback $35.00.

Rationality in Action. By John Searle. Cambridge: MIT Press, pages, ISBN Hardback $35.00. 106 AUSLEGUNG Rationality in Action. By John Searle. Cambridge: MIT Press, 2001. 303 pages, ISBN 0-262-19463-5. Hardback $35.00. Curran F. Douglass University of Kansas John Searle's Rationality in Action

More information

Merricks on the existence of human organisms

Merricks on the existence of human organisms Merricks on the existence of human organisms Cian Dorr August 24, 2002 Merricks s Overdetermination Argument against the existence of baseballs depends essentially on the following premise: BB Whenever

More information

Hard, Harder, Hardest

Hard, Harder, Hardest Hard, Harder, Hardest Katalin Balog In this paper, I will discuss three problems concerning consciousness 1. The first two problems have been dubbed The Hard Problem 2 and The Harder Problem 3. The third

More information

The UCD community has made this article openly available. Please share how this access benefits you. Your story matters!

The UCD community has made this article openly available. Please share how this access benefits you. Your story matters! Provided by the author(s) and University College Dublin Library in accordance with publisher policies., Please cite the published version when available. Title Zombies and their possibilities Authors(s)

More information

Title II: The CAPE International Conferen Philosophy of Time )

Title II: The CAPE International Conferen Philosophy of Time ) Against the illusion theory of temp Title (Proceedings of the CAPE Internatio II: The CAPE International Conferen Philosophy of Time ) Author(s) Braddon-Mitchell, David Citation CAPE Studies in Applied

More information

Philip Goff a a University of Hertfordshire. To link to this article:

Philip Goff a a University of Hertfordshire. To link to this article: This article was downloaded by: [University of Liverpool] On: 01 November 2012, At: 04:34 Publisher: Routledge Informa Ltd Registered in England and Wales Registered Number: 1072954 Registered office:

More information

Subjective Character and Reflexive Content

Subjective Character and Reflexive Content Philosophy and Phenomenological Research Vol. LXVIII, No. 1, January 2004 Subjective Character and Reflexive Content DAVID M. ROSENTHAL City University of New York Graduate Center Philosophy and Cognitive

More information

The Unsoundness of Arguments From Conceivability

The Unsoundness of Arguments From Conceivability The Unsoundness of Arguments From Conceivability Andrew Bailey Department of Philosophy The University of Guelph Guelph, Ontario N1G 2W1 Canada (519) 824-4120 x3227 abailey@uoguelph.ca 14 June 2007 ABSTRACT

More information

INTUITION AND CONSCIOUS REASONING

INTUITION AND CONSCIOUS REASONING The Philosophical Quarterly Vol. 63, No. 253 October 2013 ISSN 0031-8094 doi: 10.1111/1467-9213.12071 INTUITION AND CONSCIOUS REASONING BY OLE KOKSVIK This paper argues that, contrary to common opinion,

More information

Has Nagel uncovered a form of idealism?

Has Nagel uncovered a form of idealism? Has Nagel uncovered a form of idealism? Author: Terence Rajivan Edward, University of Manchester. Abstract. In the sixth chapter of The View from Nowhere, Thomas Nagel attempts to identify a form of idealism.

More information

Review Tutorial (A Whirlwind Tour of Metaphysics, Epistemology and Philosophy of Religion)

Review Tutorial (A Whirlwind Tour of Metaphysics, Epistemology and Philosophy of Religion) Review Tutorial (A Whirlwind Tour of Metaphysics, Epistemology and Philosophy of Religion) Arguably, the main task of philosophy is to seek the truth. We seek genuine knowledge. This is why epistemology

More information

The Possibility of Materialism

The Possibility of Materialism The Possibility of Materialism Mike Holliday Final version: 3 June 2016 1: Introduction Is a materialist account of conscious experience even possible? David Chalmers famously answered No, setting out

More information

Huemer s Problem of Memory Knowledge

Huemer s Problem of Memory Knowledge Huemer s Problem of Memory Knowledge ABSTRACT: When S seems to remember that P, what kind of justification does S have for believing that P? In "The Problem of Memory Knowledge." Michael Huemer offers

More information

Realism and instrumentalism

Realism and instrumentalism Published in H. Pashler (Ed.) The Encyclopedia of the Mind (2013), Thousand Oaks, CA: SAGE Publications, pp. 633 636 doi:10.4135/9781452257044 mark.sprevak@ed.ac.uk Realism and instrumentalism Mark Sprevak

More information

THE ANTI-ZOMBIE ARGUMENT

THE ANTI-ZOMBIE ARGUMENT The Philosophical Quarterly Vol. 57, No. 229 October 2007 ISSN 0031 8094 doi: 10.1111/j.1467-9213.2007.510.x THE ANTI-ZOMBIE ARGUMENT BY KEITH FRANKISH The zombie argument has come to occupy a central

More information

The Greatest Mistake: A Case for the Failure of Hegel s Idealism

The Greatest Mistake: A Case for the Failure of Hegel s Idealism The Greatest Mistake: A Case for the Failure of Hegel s Idealism What is a great mistake? Nietzsche once said that a great error is worth more than a multitude of trivial truths. A truly great mistake

More information

From Transcendental Logic to Transcendental Deduction

From Transcendental Logic to Transcendental Deduction From Transcendental Logic to Transcendental Deduction Let me see if I can say a few things to re-cap our first discussion of the Transcendental Logic, and help you get a foothold for what follows. Kant

More information

Chapter 11 CHALMERS' THEORY OF CONSCIOUSNESS. and yet non-reductive approach to consciousness. First, we will present the hard problem

Chapter 11 CHALMERS' THEORY OF CONSCIOUSNESS. and yet non-reductive approach to consciousness. First, we will present the hard problem Chapter 11 CHALMERS' THEORY OF CONSCIOUSNESS 1. Introduction: In this chapter we will discuss David Chalmers' attempts to formulate a scientific and yet non-reductive approach to consciousness. First,

More information

The modal status of materialism

The modal status of materialism Philos Stud (2009) 145:351 362 DOI 10.1007/s11098-008-9235-z The modal status of materialism Joseph Levine Æ Kelly Trogdon Published online: 10 May 2008 Ó Springer Science+Business Media B.V. 2008 Abstract

More information

EPIPHENOMENALISM. Keith Campbell and Nicholas J.J. Smith. December Written for the Routledge Encyclopedia of Philosophy.

EPIPHENOMENALISM. Keith Campbell and Nicholas J.J. Smith. December Written for the Routledge Encyclopedia of Philosophy. EPIPHENOMENALISM Keith Campbell and Nicholas J.J. Smith December 1993 Written for the Routledge Encyclopedia of Philosophy. Epiphenomenalism is a theory concerning the relation between the mental and physical

More information

Luck, Rationality, and Explanation: A Reply to Elga s Lucky to Be Rational. Joshua Schechter. Brown University

Luck, Rationality, and Explanation: A Reply to Elga s Lucky to Be Rational. Joshua Schechter. Brown University Luck, Rationality, and Explanation: A Reply to Elga s Lucky to Be Rational Joshua Schechter Brown University I Introduction What is the epistemic significance of discovering that one of your beliefs depends

More information

Debate on the mind and scientific method (continued again) on

Debate on the mind and scientific method (continued again) on Debate on the mind and scientific method (continued again) on http://forums.philosophyforums.com. Quotations are in red and the responses by Death Monkey (Kevin Dolan) are in black. Note that sometimes

More information

Acquaintance and the Mind-Body Problem Katalin Balog

Acquaintance and the Mind-Body Problem Katalin Balog Acquaintance and the Mind-Body Problem Katalin Balog [Penultimate draft. In: New Perspectives on Type Identity: The Mental and the Physical, Christopher Hill and Simone Gozzano (eds.), Cambridge University

More information

Is Truth the Primary Epistemic Goal? Joseph Barnes

Is Truth the Primary Epistemic Goal? Joseph Barnes Is Truth the Primary Epistemic Goal? Joseph Barnes I. Motivation: what hangs on this question? II. How Primary? III. Kvanvig's argument that truth isn't the primary epistemic goal IV. David's argument

More information

Phenomenal Knowledge, Dualism, and Dreams Jesse Butler, University of Central Arkansas

Phenomenal Knowledge, Dualism, and Dreams Jesse Butler, University of Central Arkansas Phenomenal Knowledge, Dualism, and Dreams Jesse Butler, University of Central Arkansas Dwight Holbrook (2015b) expresses misgivings that phenomenal knowledge can be regarded as both an objectless kind

More information

Contextual two-dimensionalism

Contextual two-dimensionalism Contextual two-dimensionalism phil 93507 Jeff Speaks November 30, 2009 1 Two two-dimensionalist system of The Conscious Mind.............. 1 1.1 Primary and secondary intensions...................... 2

More information

Luminosity, Reliability, and the Sorites

Luminosity, Reliability, and the Sorites Philosophy and Phenomenological Research Vol. LXXXI No. 3, November 2010 2010 Philosophy and Phenomenological Research, LLC Luminosity, Reliability, and the Sorites STEWART COHEN University of Arizona

More information

1/7. The Postulates of Empirical Thought

1/7. The Postulates of Empirical Thought 1/7 The Postulates of Empirical Thought This week we are focusing on the final section of the Analytic of Principles in which Kant schematizes the last set of categories. This set of categories are what

More information

What does McGinn think we cannot know?

What does McGinn think we cannot know? What does McGinn think we cannot know? Exactly what is McGinn (1991) saying when he claims that we cannot solve the mind-body problem? Just what is cognitively closed to us? The text suggests at least

More information

SUPPOSITIONAL REASONING AND PERCEPTUAL JUSTIFICATION

SUPPOSITIONAL REASONING AND PERCEPTUAL JUSTIFICATION SUPPOSITIONAL REASONING AND PERCEPTUAL JUSTIFICATION Stewart COHEN ABSTRACT: James Van Cleve raises some objections to my attempt to solve the bootstrapping problem for what I call basic justification

More information

Overcoming Cartesian Intuitions: A Defense of Type-Physicalism

Overcoming Cartesian Intuitions: A Defense of Type-Physicalism Indiana Undergraduate Journal of Cognitive Science 4 (2009) 81-96 Copyright 2009 IUJCS. All rights reserved Overcoming Cartesian Intuitions: A Defense of Type-Physicalism Ronald J. Planer Rutgers University

More information

Materialism and the Metaphysics of Modality

Materialism and the Metaphysics of Modality Philosophy and Phenomenological Research Vol. LIX, No.2, June 1999 Materialism and the Metaphysics of Modality DAVID J. CHALMERS University ofarizona Contents 1 Introduction 2 A priori entailment (Shoemaker)

More information

Supervenience, and. Deep Ignorance, Brute. Problem of the Many. the. Terry Horgan. 16 Truth, 1997

Supervenience, and. Deep Ignorance, Brute. Problem of the Many. the. Terry Horgan. 16 Truth, 1997 PHILOSOPHICAL ISSUES, 8 16 Truth, 1997 Deep Ignorance, Brute Supervenience, and Problem of the Many the Terry Horgan Timothy Williamson holds that vagueness, properly understood, is an epistemic phenomenon:

More information

Reductive explanation and the explanatory gap

Reductive explanation and the explanatory gap Reductive explanation and the explanatory gap Peter Carruthers Department of Philosophy University of Maryland, College Park MD 20742, USA Can phenomenal consciousness be given a reductive natural explanation?

More information

Consciousness Without Awareness

Consciousness Without Awareness Consciousness Without Awareness Eric Saidel Department of Philosophy Box 43770 University of Southwestern Louisiana Lafayette, LA 70504-3770 USA saidel@usl.edu Copyright (c) Eric Saidel 1999 PSYCHE, 5(16),

More information

In Defense of Radical Empiricism. Joseph Benjamin Riegel. Chapel Hill 2006

In Defense of Radical Empiricism. Joseph Benjamin Riegel. Chapel Hill 2006 In Defense of Radical Empiricism Joseph Benjamin Riegel A thesis submitted to the faculty of the University of North Carolina at Chapel Hill in partial fulfillment of the requirements for the degree of

More information

Each copy of any part of a JSTOR transmission must contain the same copyright notice that appears on the screen or printed page of such transmission.

Each copy of any part of a JSTOR transmission must contain the same copyright notice that appears on the screen or printed page of such transmission. Review: Concepts and Consciousness Author(s): Stephen Yablo Reviewed work(s): The Conscious Mind by David Chalmers Source: Philosophy and Phenomenological Research, Vol. 59, No. 2, (Jun., 1999), pp. 455-463

More information

Does the Skeptic Win? A Defense of Moore. I. Moorean Methodology. In A Proof of the External World, Moore argues as follows:

Does the Skeptic Win? A Defense of Moore. I. Moorean Methodology. In A Proof of the External World, Moore argues as follows: Does the Skeptic Win? A Defense of Moore I argue that Moore s famous response to the skeptic should be accepted even by the skeptic. My paper has three main stages. First, I will briefly outline G. E.

More information

McDowell and the New Evil Genius

McDowell and the New Evil Genius 1 McDowell and the New Evil Genius Ram Neta and Duncan Pritchard 0. Many epistemologists both internalists and externalists regard the New Evil Genius Problem (Lehrer & Cohen 1983) as constituting an important

More information

DISCUSSION THE GUISE OF A REASON

DISCUSSION THE GUISE OF A REASON NADEEM J.Z. HUSSAIN DISCUSSION THE GUISE OF A REASON The articles collected in David Velleman s The Possibility of Practical Reason are a snapshot or rather a film-strip of part of a philosophical endeavour

More information

Many Minds are No Worse than One

Many Minds are No Worse than One Replies 233 Many Minds are No Worse than One David Papineau 1 Introduction 2 Consciousness 3 Probability 1 Introduction The Everett-style interpretation of quantum mechanics developed by Michael Lockwood

More information

Must we have self-evident knowledge if we know anything?

Must we have self-evident knowledge if we know anything? 1 Must we have self-evident knowledge if we know anything? Introduction In this essay, I will describe Aristotle's account of scientific knowledge as given in Posterior Analytics, before discussing some

More information

Understanding, Modality, Logical Operators. Christopher Peacocke. Columbia University

Understanding, Modality, Logical Operators. Christopher Peacocke. Columbia University Understanding, Modality, Logical Operators Christopher Peacocke Columbia University Timothy Williamson s The Philosophy of Philosophy stimulates on every page. I would like to discuss every chapter. To

More information

Thomas Nagel, "What is it Like to Be a Bat?", The Philosophical Review 83 (1974),

Thomas Nagel, What is it Like to Be a Bat?, The Philosophical Review 83 (1974), Bats, Brain Scientists, and the Limitations of Introspection Philosophy and Phenomenological Research 54 (1994), pp. 315-329 Derk Pereboom, University of Vermont Thomas Nagel and Frank Jackson have advanced

More information

A Posteriori Necessities by Saul Kripke (excerpted from Naming and Necessity, 1980)

A Posteriori Necessities by Saul Kripke (excerpted from Naming and Necessity, 1980) A Posteriori Necessities by Saul Kripke (excerpted from Naming and Necessity, 1980) Let's suppose we refer to the same heavenly body twice, as 'Hesperus' and 'Phosphorus'. We say: Hesperus is that star

More information

Mental Files and their Identity Conditions

Mental Files and their Identity Conditions Mental Files and their Identity Conditions University of Oxford BIBLID [0873-626X (2013) 36; pp. 177-190] It is increasingly common for a thinker s capacity for singular thought to be described in terms

More information

Outsmarting the McKinsey-Brown argument? 1

Outsmarting the McKinsey-Brown argument? 1 Outsmarting the McKinsey-Brown argument? 1 Paul Noordhof Externalists about mental content are supposed to face the following dilemma. Either they must give up the claim that we have privileged access

More information

Boghossian & Harman on the analytic theory of the a priori

Boghossian & Harman on the analytic theory of the a priori Boghossian & Harman on the analytic theory of the a priori PHIL 83104 November 2, 2011 Both Boghossian and Harman address themselves to the question of whether our a priori knowledge can be explained in

More information

CAUSAL-RECOGNITIONAL ACCOUNT OF PHENOMENAL CONCEPTS: AN ALTERNATIVE PHYSICALIST ATTEMPT TO SOLVE THE PROBLEM OF CONSCIOUSNESS

CAUSAL-RECOGNITIONAL ACCOUNT OF PHENOMENAL CONCEPTS: AN ALTERNATIVE PHYSICALIST ATTEMPT TO SOLVE THE PROBLEM OF CONSCIOUSNESS CAUSAL-RECOGNITIONAL ACCOUNT OF PHENOMENAL CONCEPTS: AN ALTERNATIVE PHYSICALIST ATTEMPT TO SOLVE THE PROBLEM OF CONSCIOUSNESS Adeyanju Olanshile Muideen Obafemi Awolowo University, Ile-Ife Abstract This

More information

Projection in Hume. P J E Kail. St. Peter s College, Oxford.

Projection in Hume. P J E Kail. St. Peter s College, Oxford. Projection in Hume P J E Kail St. Peter s College, Oxford Peter.kail@spc.ox.ac.uk A while ago now (2007) I published my Projection and Realism in Hume s Philosophy (Oxford University Press henceforth abbreviated

More information

Logic and Pragmatics: linear logic for inferential practice

Logic and Pragmatics: linear logic for inferential practice Logic and Pragmatics: linear logic for inferential practice Daniele Porello danieleporello@gmail.com Institute for Logic, Language & Computation (ILLC) University of Amsterdam, Plantage Muidergracht 24

More information

Annotated Bibliography. seeking to keep the possibility of dualism alive in academic study. In this book,

Annotated Bibliography. seeking to keep the possibility of dualism alive in academic study. In this book, Warren 1 Koby Warren PHIL 400 Dr. Alfino 10/30/2010 Annotated Bibliography Chalmers, David John. The conscious mind: in search of a fundamental theory.! New York: Oxford University Press, 1996. Print.!

More information

5 A Modal Version of the

5 A Modal Version of the 5 A Modal Version of the Ontological Argument E. J. L O W E Moreland, J. P.; Sweis, Khaldoun A.; Meister, Chad V., Jul 01, 2013, Debating Christian Theism The original version of the ontological argument

More information

An Inferentialist Conception of the A Priori. Ralph Wedgwood

An Inferentialist Conception of the A Priori. Ralph Wedgwood An Inferentialist Conception of the A Priori Ralph Wedgwood When philosophers explain the distinction between the a priori and the a posteriori, they usually characterize the a priori negatively, as involving

More information

In Meaning and Truth, J. Campbell, M. O Rourke, and D. Shier, eds. (New York: Seven Bridges Press, 2001):

In Meaning and Truth, J. Campbell, M. O Rourke, and D. Shier, eds. (New York: Seven Bridges Press, 2001): In Meaning and Truth, J. Campbell, M. O Rourke, and D. Shier, eds. (New York: Seven Bridges Press, 2001): 34-52. THE SEMANTIC BASIS OF EXTERNALISM Michael McKinsey Wayne State University 1. The primary

More information