On Taking Precepts to Belong to Social Morality [Do Not Cite]

Size: px
Start display at page:

Download "On Taking Precepts to Belong to Social Morality [Do Not Cite]"

Transcription

1 1 On Taking Precepts to Belong to Social Morality [Do Not Cite] Everyone must grant that a law, if it to hold morally, that is, as a ground of an obligation, must carry with it absolute necessity that, therefore, the ground of obligation here must not be sought in the nature of the human being or in the circumstances of the world in which he is placed, but a priori simply in the concepts of pure reason; and that any other precept, which is based on principles of mere experience even if it is universal in a certain respect insofar as it rests in the least part on empirical grounds can indeed be a called a practical rule but never a moral law. 1 Jerry s project concerns the justification of social morality. I am interested in what social morality is. More specifically, I m interested in what makes it social and what makes it morality. I hope by getting clearer about these matters in my own mind that I will be able to pin down how the problem of its justification arises. I ll then be able to suggest an alternative solution to that problem and say to what I think the alternative has to recommend it. The power of Jerry s extraordinarily interesting book is derived in part from the breadth of its range and from the intricacy of its argument. I cannot claim to have mastered the book, I am aware of how much I am passing over in silence and I almost certainly have many things wrong. I hope that those who know the book better than I will indulge me. On p. 2 of his book, Jerry says: SM: By social morality I mean the set of social-moral rules that require or prohibit action, and so ground moral imperatives that we direct to each other to engage in, or refrain from, certain lines of conduct. (p. 2) This description is a conjunction. What is the set of social moral rules with which the first conjunct identifies social morality? First, it is a set of social-moral rules, so it is a set of moral rules. These rules express moral rights and duties, moral prohibitions and permissions. They are rules the violation of which is, or is thought to be, morally wrong. Moreover, it is a set of social-moral rules rather than social-moral principles. Rules differ from first principles of morality by their specificity. (pp. 42, 180, 271) What makes the rules of social morality specific is that they refer to particular action-types. Some of Jerry s examples of rules which are included or putatively included in social morality concern truth-telling and lying (p. 302), marital fidelity (p. 44), privacy (p. 302), smoking behavior (p. 316) and voluntary euthanasia (p. 245) What is meant by saying that it is a set of social moral rules? What makes social morality social? Jerry s examples suggest one answer: that social morality concerns interpersonal conduct. I believe Jerry thinks that the rules of what he calls the true social morality (pp. 179, 425, 430, 434) will be social in that they concern only such conduct. But people sometimes take rules about selfregarding conduct to belong to social morality also. That they do brings me to the second conjunct of Jerry s description and to another sense in which social morality is social. 1 Immanuel Kant, Groundwork, 4:389 (trans. Gregor)

2 2 The second conjunct of SM refers to the fact that we direct moral imperatives to one another. The direction of imperatives to one another is, Jerry says in one passage, an actual practice (p. xvi), a practice in which we all actually engage. In that passage, Jerry identifies morality with this practice rather than with a set of rules. A terminological distinction will help us keep things straight. Let s use the phrase practice of social morality to refer to the practice of issuing imperatives which express the rules we take to belong to the set of rules with which social morality is identified in SM. One thing that makes the practice social is that we direct the imperatives to one another. The rules of social morality are then social in a second sense because they have a role in a social practice. When I said that Jerry s project concerns the justification of social morality, I meant that it concerns the justification of rules of social morality. Questions about justification might be thought to arise because, as I suggested a moment ago, people engaged in the practice of social morality are sometimes wrong, or can sometimes be wrong, about what rules really do belong to the true social morality. They mistakenly take some rules to belong to social morality which don t one of Jerry s examples is an anti-smoking rule (p. 320), but we might add lots of classic examples of rules about self-regarding actions -- and direct imperatives to others that are in fact ungrounded. The direction of ungrounded imperatives is a problem, for reasons to which I shall return. And this problem seems to motivate Jerry s project by raising the question of what rules of social morality are justified. 2 One way to address that question, and to dispel the motivational problem, would be to identify the rules that belong to the true social morality. But Jerry proceeds differently. He thinks that a rule belongs to the true social morality only if it can be verified more specifically, only if it can be verified from the requisite moral point of view. (p. 2) It can be verified from that point of view only if it can be publicly justified. (see pp , for example) And so Jerry identifies and defends conditions on the public justification. These conditions enable us to test[] (p. 177) rules that we take to belong to social morality. They provide a constraint (pp. 19, 401) that rules must satisfy if they are part of true social morality, so that we can determine whether the imperatives we consider directing to one another are properly grounded. Note that the way I have discussed the motivation of Jerry s project so far suggests that our taking rules to belong to social morality is crucial. I m puzzled by and interested in what this means, and I want to spend some time thinking through it. 1. Three Additional Features of Social Morality A necessary condition of our taking rules to belong to social morality would seem to be that we who engage in the practice of social morality have the concepts of a rule and a practice of social morality, for only if we do can we take or mistake their applications. Only if we have these concepts can we take some rules to be part of social morality which in fact are not. One problem with supposing that we do have these concepts is that social morality has other important features besides those I have cited so far. 3 2 Jerry writes: [Kurt Baier s morality] is our real practice, which makes your activities your neighbor s business; he calls on morality to tell you what to do, and he will not simply shrug his shoulders and walk away if you ignore his demands. Confronting this actual practice in which imperfect compliance is a central feature we have to ask why do we need it? and when can its claims to authority be freely recognized by all? These are the questions I seek to answer in this work. (p. xvi) 3 See the features listed by Kevin Vallier on 1/17/11 at:

3 3 (1) Social morality understood as both rules and the practice -- is just a part of the ethical, and is distinct from that part which concerns ideals and perfectionist values. (p. 3) (2) The rules of social morality are moral rules applying to a large-scale moral order in which we often confront others as strangers what F.A. Hayek called The Great Society. the rules that govern our interactions when we know little about the other, except that she is a moral person. (p. 268) (3) The practice of social morality is said to be the foundation of social existence (p. 255) and to be necessary for cooperative social life. (p. 22, emphasis added) The necessity of the practice of directing imperatives has implications for what rules actually ground imperatives. (p. 22) I believe Jerry thinks that if a rule belongs to social morality, then the general adherence to the rule itself must be necessary for cooperative social life. (see pp. 22, 282) So to have the requisite concepts, and to be able to take some rule to belong to the rules of social morality, we must grasp a sophisticated distinction within the ethical. And we must grasp the conceptual connection between issuing an imperative which expresses the rule and the necessity of general adherence to that rule for social cooperation. But if this is required, then I am not sure that the notion of social morality will be in many people s vocabulary or conceptual repertoire. For I am not at all sure that when people take some rule to ground a moral imperative which they direct to others, they take that rule to be necessary for a social life that counts as cooperative. They may recognize that general adherence to the rule isn t necessary or essential for that. But they may blur the distinction within the ethical, believe that social life would just be better if people observed the rule, perhaps for perfectionist reasons, and direct an imperative that expresses it. This problem with the notion of morality stems from the third of the three additional features of social morality that I just listed. Jerry takes social morality to have that feature because of one of his most powerful animating ideas: that the contents of morality depend upon what human beings need morality for. 4 But though the insight is very illuminating, if we build the necessity claim into the concept of social morality by identifying social morality with rules that are needed for cooperation, we are forced to concede that many people lack the concept. In that case, it will be hard to see how people can take rules to belong to the rules of social morality and how the motivating problem of Jerry s project can properly be described. So perhaps it s better to think of things this way. The rules of social morality are social in part because they apply to social existence. Someone who takes a precept to belong to the rules of social morality takes it to apply to social existence. It seems clear enough that the concept of a rule which applies to social existence is widely shared, so there is no conceptual barrier to our motivating Jerry s project by saying that taking precepts to belong to social morality is something 4 For an especially clear and compelling statement, see p Jerry draws the epigraphs of this book from three thinkers who share the insight: Strawson, Hayek and Baier. As I read the book, I had the recurring thought that he could instead have chosen one of my own favorite pieces of moral philosophy, which also expresses that insight, a verse from the Gospel of Mark: The Sabbath was made for man and not man for the Sabbath. (2:27)

4 4 lots of people do. But the stronger claim that the rules of social morality are just those ethical precepts that are necessary to coordinate social existence is a very powerful conclusion that, if true, must follow from premises about public justification and about the nature of coordination and cooperation. It is not a claim that is built into or follows immediately from the meaning of social morality or that has to be grasped for people to have the concept. I said earlier that Jerry s project might seem to be motivated by the fact that participants in the practice of social morality are or can be mistaken about what precepts belong to the rules of social morality, and direct ungrounded imperatives to one another. I put off saying why their doing so is problematic and why their doing so raises questions of justification. I now want to return to those questions. To answer them, it will help to get a bit clearer on the parts of our social existence to which the rules of social morality taken to apply. According to the second of the three additional features of social morality, the rules of social morality are moral rules applying to a large-scale moral order in which we often confront others as strangers what F.A. Hayek called The Great Society. the rules that govern our interactions when we know little about the other, except that she is a moral person. (p. 268) If this feature is part of the concept of social morality, then someone who takes a precept to belong to social morality must take it to be such a rule. This may tempt us to read Jerry as saying that when someone takes a precept to belong to social morality, she takes it to be a rule which is social in this sense: it applies only to Hayek s Great Society, that it applies only to a large-scale moral order in which we often confront others as strangers, and that it govern[s] [only] our interactions when we know little about the other, except that she is a moral person. That is, it may tempt us to read Jerry as distinguishing social morality from the morality of marriage or friendship or special relationships and to suppose that we who engage in the practice of social morality take a different set of rules to ground the imperatives we address or the demands we make in those relationships. 5 But I do not think this is what Jerry wants to say. That he does not want to say it becomes clear, I think, when we return to the question of what motivates jerry s project. In an important passage in the preface, Jerry implies that someone involved in the practice of social morality: calls on morality to tell you what to do, and he will not simply shrug his shoulders and walk away if you ignore his demands. (p. xvi, emphasis added) Rather, he blames, punishes, is indignant, and so on at their refusal to comply. (p. xv) Jerry implies later that few of us have the strength of will to be un-phased by the prospect of incurring these sanctions. (pp ) Taken together, these passages suggest a way of describing the motivating problem of Jerry s project is and how the question of justification arises. The direction of imperatives that express rules we take to belong to social morality is often accompanied by acts or threats of coercion because penalties are often attached to violation of the imperatives. That, we might think, is the motivating problem. That this is the motivating problem seems to be confirmed by the fact that Jerry says [s]ocial morality raises problems similar to the traditional problems of liberal political philosophy. (p. 48) In both cases, we need to know under what conditions acts or threats 5 I think this is the way Kevin Vallier and Blain Neufeld read Jerry in their exchange of 1/28/11 at:

5 5 of coercion are justified. Jerry seems to address that question as it pertains to social morality by defending a constraint on rules which can be expressed to imperatives to coercion is attached. State coercion raises a problem for liberal political philosophy because such coercion is, for practical purposes, inescapable. Jerry would have the strongest case for his assertion of a similarity between that problem and the problems raised by the practice of social morality, and the strongest motivation for his project, if the sanctions attached to imperatives of social morality were similarly inescapable. One way he might argue that that they are inescapable is by arguing that they, or the imperatives to which they are attached, are pervasive. The argument that the imperatives and sanctions are pervasive will be much easier to make if participants in the practice of social morality generally take the rules of social morality to govern special relationships as well as relations with strangers and distant others. And that is just what Jerry seems to think. When he argues for the burdensomeness of sanctions attached to the imperatives which are addressed to us, he does not refer to the imperatives addressed to us by strangers (p. 268) and distant others. He says And if we thought that we would get a good talking to from our disapproving friends or employer, this would be a very significant deterrent to acting on our standards. (pp , emphasis added) It may be that the true social morality consists of just those rules that have the second feature of social morality. That is, it may be that the true social morality consists of just those moral rules applying to a large-scale moral order in which we often confront others as strangers what F.A. Hayek called The Great Society. the rules that govern our interactions when we know little about the other, except that she is a moral person. (p. 268) And so it may be that the truth about social morality is that the first additional feature asserts just one of the important distinctions within the ethical. But as with the third additional feature so with the second, the claim that social morality has it must be a conclusion that follows from premises about public justification and cooperation, and not a feature that is built into the concept of social morality. Let me add parenthetically that I do not think Jerry s text forces us to impute this conclusion to him. For the passage which expresses the second additional feature of social morality does not say that the rules of social morality govern [only] our interactions when we know little about the other, except that she is a moral person. I have said that it is tempting to read it that way. But another way to read it is as intentionally leaving open the possibility that the rules of social morality apply and are taken to apply to large stretches of our social life, while drawing attention to the description of us under which the rules of social morality must be justified to us namely, as moral persons. 6 Our moral personality may be what enables us take part in Hayek s Great Society and in moral relations with strangers, but I think it is also engaged in special relationships. If that is right, then perhaps it is that in virtue of which the true rules of social morality apply to those relationships as well. 2. Still Another Feature of Social Morality The motivation of Jerry s project may now seem to be fairly clearly in view. We participate in an on-going practice of social morality. Our participation consists in this: As SM says, we direct imperatives to each other to engage in, or refrain from, certain lines of conduct. We may direct those imperatives to strangers or to distant others, but we also address them to our intimates and friends and employees. The direction of those imperatives comes with the implied threat of sanctions for their violation. Because of the large stretches of social life to which the rules of social morality are generally taken to apply, such threats and sanctions are inescapable. Because of the 6 See Gerald Gaus, The Moral Foundations of Liberal Neutrality, Contemporary Debates in Political Philosophy (Wiley-Blackwell, 2009), pp , p. 87.

6 6 burdensomeness and inescapability of the threats and sanctions generally attached to imperatives, we need to see under what conditions we are justified in directing imperatives to one another. Jerry says much that suggest this way of thinking about his motivation, and I have drawn on passages that seem to support it. But Jerry says other things that suggest a different and, to my mind, a deeper and more interesting motivation. This motivation is connected not with what Jerry thinks makes social morality social, but with what he thinks makes it morality. Morality, Jerry writes, is about making demands on others. (p. 266) More precisely but less memorably, he says that [a]t the heart of social morality is a fundamental claim to authority over others. (p. 8) This latter remark adds still another feature to social morality. For SM says By social morality I mean the set of social-moral rules that require or prohibit action, and so ground moral imperatives that we direct to each other to engage in, or refrain from, certain lines of conduct. (p. 2) In light of his remark about the heart of social morality, I now think that what Jerry means by SM is not just, as I conjectured earlier and as the wording of SM suggests, that if I take some rule to belong to social morality, then I take it to ground a binding imperative which expresses it. I also take it to ground an authority of mine: I take myself to be authorized to direct that imperative to others and authorized to imply that they may justifiably be sanctioned for its violation. Jerry says this especially clearly in a recent paper. There he writes: If I decide that your action falls under the purview of social morality, I see it as my business that you refrain from -ing. I claim authority over you in the sense of claiming a standing to direct your action. 7 I read this passage as concerning, or as having implications for, what is involved in taking a rule that prohibits -ing to belong to social morality. So I take it as committing Jerry to: TC: If I take the rule that prohibits -ing to belong to social morality, then I see it as my business that you refrain from -ing. I claim authority over you in the sense of claiming a standing to direct your action. I shall refer to this claim again, and so it will be convenient to assign it a name. Let s name it after a passage that is much beloved of libertarians. Let s call it the Takings Clause. If Jerry does indeed accept the Takings Clause, then the motivating problem of his project is not that inescapable sanctions are generally attached to the imperatives we issue. Rather, it is agreed all around that we need some kind of rules to say how our life together should be carried on or how it would be good for our life to be carried on. According to the Takings Clause, the very act of taking a precept to be one of those rules entails that the taker claims authority to direct others to comply with the precept even, I think, in cases where the taker is not party to the transaction to which the precept is taken to apply. Authority claims always need to be justified. So the motivating problem of Jerry s project is that while people claim authority over others by the acts of taking rules to belong to social morality, they often are or can be wrong about when they are justified in claiming it. Jerry addresses this problem by identifying a constraint on rules that can justifiably be taken to belong to social morality, and so a constraint on justified authority claims. His project resembles 7 Gerald Gaus, Justification, Choice and Promise, p. 5.

7 7 then liberal political philosophy, not in assuming that threats of coercion have to be justified, but in assuming that authority claims have to be. But why do authority claims always need to be justified? To draw out the parallel with political theory, if someone on a radio-call in show claims to be the King of America, I don t ask if his authority-claim over me or his directives are justified. The question never crosses my mind. I simply ignore him. Similarly, if someone on a radio call-in show says that college professors and Rawlsian liberals are immoral, I don t ask if he has justified authority to direct my action. I simply ignore him. Grant for the moment that in taking a precept against being a college professor to belong to social morality, the caller is lodging an authority claim over me. I simply do not care about authority claims made over me by distant strangers. Jerry says early in the book that it is unacceptable to ignore moral demands. (p. 12) Such demands, he continues, cannot be blamelessly ignored. (p. 12) I am not sure why he says thinks I cannot blamelessly ignore the radio caller. It certainly seems to me that I can. But perhaps Jerry would say that I do not ignore him. What I really do when I think I ignore him is assume that his authority claim is unjustified. In doing so, Jerry might say, I simply assume that the precept against being a college professor is unjustified. I have therefore help myself to just the kind of constraint on public justification that Jerry is trying to identify and defend. If I have not ignored the radio caller then I do not know what kind of cases Jerry s claim about the unacceptability of ignoring moral demands is meant to prohibit. But let that pass. Though Jerry says that his book seek[s] to answer questions raised by our actual practice in which imperfect compliance is a central feature (p. xvi), I do not think we need cases of imperfect compliance like the radio caller to raise the questions and problems that really motivate Jerry s project. For even if the only authority claims that were ever made were justified, we would still want to understand what makes them so. If, as Jerry asserts, we need social morality to coordinate our social life and if, as the Takings Clause asserts, taking a precept to belong to social morality entails a claim of authority, then we would want to understand how authority is connected to our needs even if all such takings were justified. This points to another similarity between the problems of social morality and the traditional problems of liberal political philosophy (p. 48): in the analysis of social morality as in the analysis of social justice, perfect compliance theory is puzzling enough. 3. Is the Clause True? If I have read Jerry correctly, then the motivation of his project depends crucially upon the truth of the Takings Clause. But I am not altogether sure that the Clause is true. To see the reason for my doubts, let s consider a proposition that is equivalent to the Takings Clause, its contraposition: TC CP: If it s not the case that I see it as my business that you refrain from -ing if it s not the case that I claim authority over you in the sense of claiming a standing to direct your action then it s not the case that I take the rule that prohibits -ing to belong to social morality. I do not think TC CP is true. For suppose that the antecedent is true and that it s not the case that I claim authority over some person B with respect to his marital fidelity or claim standing to direct him in the conduct of his marriage. It doesn t seem to follow that I don t take rules prohibiting infidelity as belonging to social morality. Mightn t I take those rules to belong to social morality, but think that it falls to B s spouse H, or his friends, or his pastor, to direct his behavior and call

8 8 him to account for his infidelity? Mightn t I think that B wronged H by betraying her, but that it is not my business to tell him so? More generally: Most of us, I have supposed, have the concept of social morality. I suggested that we do not have the robust concept that Jerry introduces, but have granted that we have something of the concept even so. I am also supposing that for each of us, there are some precepts she takes to belong to social morality. Mightn t each of us also think that the practices of issuing imperatives to one another which express the precepts we take to belong to social morality, of directing one another s behavior and of calling one another to account for misbehavior, are governed by conventions which assign authority and responsibility to for doing these things to some people but not to others? If so, then the negation of the consequent of the Takings Clause can be true while the negation of the antecedent is false, and the Takings Clause itself is false. I think this line of reasoning also shows the falsity of the Takings Clause even if we grant Jerry the more robust concept of social morality and suppose that everyone has it. So suppose that for each person, there are precepts which he takes to belong to social morality because he thinks their general observance by distant others is necessary for social coordination. Suppose further that each person thinks social coordination is possible only if there are practices of directing others to observe those precepts and of calling them to account when they don t. Mightn t each person also think that society meets its need for these practices by devising conventions which apportion the labor of directing and calling to account, assigning that labor to intimates, friends and those in special social roles such as pastor and policeman? These considerations show that we need to amend the Takings Clause something Rawlsian liberals are accused of wanting to do anyway. 8 The Clause might be amended to read: TC : If I take the rule that prohibits -ing to belong to social morality, then I see it as someone s business that you refrain from -ing. I think someone can claim authority over you in the sense of claiming a standing to direct your action. The considerations that force this amendment raise a possibility that I want to pursue. Before I do so, let me just note that the plausibility of TC seems to me to turn on a deep question of what we might call moral phenomenology on which I believe philosophers are divided. I am sorry that I can only explain the division crudely, but it seems to me to be this. Jerry, I am supposing for the moment, regards the amendment to the Takings Clause as friendly and accepts the amended version. Other philosophers agree with him that we cannot take some precept to belong to social morality without at the same taking ourselves to be in the presence of authority, but they do not think that that authority is anybody s. Rather, they think, we cannot take a precept to belong to social morality without taking ourselves to be in the presence of the moral law. The authority we experience when we apprehend some precept as belonging to social morality is the authority of morality itself. Jerry puts aside inquiry into the sources of normativity, implying that it is too theoretical to bear on the questions that interest him. (p. 4) I conjecture that what Jerry really thinks is suggested by 8 See Leif Wenar, The Concept of Property and the Takings Clause, Columbia Law Review 97 (1997): , p. 1934f.

9 9 another remark early in his book: Morality does not directly speak to us; it is other people who speak to us, asserting their view of morality as demands that we act as they see fit. (p. xvi) The problem with inquiry into the sources of normativity, he thinks, is that it is premised on denial of both versions of the Takings Clause and on the claim that morality does directly speak to us. Such inquiry begins with the thought that we cannot take ourselves to be subject to a moral precept without at the same time experiencing as Kant implied in the passage which stands at the head of my paper -- a kind of impersonal necessity, the source of which moral philosophy has to explain. If this is right, then Jerry s philosophical differences with, e.g. Chris Korsgaard, are not ultimately differences about the level of abstraction at which each thinks moral philosophy should operate. Rather, those differences can be traced to differences about the interpretation of primitive moral experience. I incline to the Korsgaardian interpretation. But I do not know how to settle these differences, or to determine whether the amended Takings Clause is right, except to see whose overall account of morality is most persuasive. To that end, let me return to the motivation of Jerry s project and the considerations that led to the amendment of the Takings Clause. 4, Second-Order Precepts The motivating problem of Jerry s project, I have argued, arises because people claim authority to direct the action of others and their directions express precepts that they take to belong to social morality. Jerry tries to identify the conditions under which such authority claims are justified. I have said that he does so by identifying a condition or constraint that precepts must satisfy if they are to belong to the true social morality. Then I am justified in issuing an imperative to someone not to smoke only if a precept prohibiting smoking under the circumstances satisfies the constraint. I am justified in issuing imperatives to others not to engage in certain kinds of sexual conduct only if a precept prohibiting such conduct satisfies the constraint. These precepts concerning smoking and sex, like the examples that occur throughout Jerry s book, are what we might call first-order precepts. They prescribe conduct, but not conduct constitutive of the practice of social morality itself. When I asked about the truth of the Takings Clause, I pointed out that the practice might be governed by conventions that govern that conduct by allocating responsibility for issuing imperatives and calling one another to account. Call these conventions second-order precepts. Let s consider the possibility of a system of second-order precepts that implements the amended version of the Takings Clause, a system that governs who can issue to directives to whom to do what. The possibility of such a system suggests another way to address the motivating problem of Jerry s project. Instead of looking into the justifiability of first-order precepts, we might argue that authority to direct another s conduct has to be conferred by a justified system of second-order precepts, and we can look into what system of second-order precepts is justified. If it turns out that I ought not issue directives to B about his smoking or his sexual behavior, that will be because publicly justified set of second-order precepts would not allow people in my position to do that. And if no one is to issue directives to anyone else about certain behaviors, that will be because publicly justified second-order precepts would not allow anyone to issue such imperatives. On the proposal I am now considering, nothing about the first-order content of morality is entailed by facts about what imperatives can and cannot be justifiably directed to others. We have conventions according to which there are some questions we do not direct to others. We do not, for example, inquire about the latest occupational successes of others ne er-do-well sons. Nothing follows about the morality of being a ne er-do-well. Perhaps justifiable conventions according to which there are imperatives we do not direct imperatives to others are similar. Perhaps pressing the imperatives, like pressing certain inquiries, is simply not done. It is in poor taste. If so, no

10 10 more would follow about the morality of the behavior about which we refrain from directing than follows about the morality of conduct we refrain from asking about. I shall not go so far as to draw that conclusion. But given the way Jerry understands public justification, I am drawn to the attempt to address Jerry s motivating problem by asking about the justifiability of second- rather than of first-order precepts. I am uncomfortable with the unqualified identification of morality, or some part of morality, with the set precepts that can be publicly justified in Jerry s sense. I shall try to make the nature and source of the discomfort clearer, and to show how it might be alleviated if Jerry s motivating problem is addressed in the way I have suggested. I shall do so by posing a question the phrasing of which is suggested by Jerry s assertion of a similarity between the problem posed by social morality and problems faced by liberal political philosophy. 5. Justification and Legitimacy Even in a just society, the law may permit what some citizens think justice forbids. To take one of Rawls s examples, a well-ordered society may adopt a liberal abortion regime. Some members of that society may believe that an abortion commits an injustice against the fetus, so they believe that abortion is a legally permissible injustice. This case raises a question about which I think liberal political philosophy should be deeply concerned, for reasons I shall not go into here: what conclusions are these people to draw about the moral permissibility of abortion from the fact that abortion is legally permissible? Are they to think that permissibility is on the side of the law, so they are to believe abortion is unjust by morally permissible? Are they to think that permissibility follows justice, so that the law permits something which is morally wrong? The first option strikes me as incoherent as it stands. Without further explanation, I do not see how an action could be unjust but permissible, for the unqualified claim that an action is unjust seems to me to entail that one is under at least a prima facie obligation to refrain from performing it. One way of removing the incoherence would be to distinguish two realms of morality. The idea would be something like this: Citizens of a pluralistic society will have diverse moralities which they use to govern their own lives, according to some of which abortion is unjust. Liberal political philosophy recognizes this. But it also holds that our common life must be governed by laws which are mutually justifiable. Since a blanket prohibition on abortion could not be mutually justified, the law must permit abortion. And since the must in the premise our common life must be governed by laws which are mutually justifiable is a moral must, the legal permissibility of abortion follows from moral imperative. So, the liberal political philosopher might be thought to conclude, there is a sense of morally permissible in which citizens have to recognize abortion as morally permissible after all. It is wrong according to one moral code but not wrong according to another. That liberals bifurcate morality in this way is suggested by the contrast which is sometimes drawn between political morality or public morality and private morality. I think this way of handling the case is a mistake, since the bifurcation of morality is a controversial philosophical move at odds with many citizens moral views. Many citizens may think that if moral prohibitions are valid, as they take those of their comprehensive views to be, then the

11 11 prohibited actions are unqualifiedly wrong and therefore unqualifiedly impermissible, at least prima facie. They therefore disagree with the claim that there are two senses of morally wrong and morally permissible. If liberals want to resist making such moves, they ought instead to handle the case in the second way. I assume they do want to avoid making so controversial a move, and I think can handle Rawls s example by exercising the second option. On the second option as on the first, our common life must be governed by laws which are mutually justifiable. A well-ordered society satisfies that condition. So the citizens of Rawls s example, who live in a well-ordered society, can believe that a liberal abortion law permits behavior which is morally wrong, perhaps gravely wrong, but they are to think that it the law -- is justifiable even so. The question is how this is possible. That question becomes more troubling if we assume that a law which permits grave injustices is an unjust law. For then the citizens in the example are to regard the law as justifiable even though it is unjust. How can that be? I take the Rawlsian liberal response to be that justice is not the only justificatory concept available and that just is not the only justificatory predicate that can be ascribed to a law. If a justificatory concept can be found that is less demanding than justice, then a law could be, and could be regarded as, justified even if it allows acts that unjust by some people s lights and even if they regard the law as, in that respect, an unjust law. I take it that legitimacy is such a concept. To show that a law is legitimate, or that its enactment was a legitimate exercise of political power, is to show that the law enjoys a kind of justification even if it is not just. Moreover, because of legitimacy s connections which I assume here with the government s right to command and with citizen s duties of obedience and non-resistance, the justification associated with legitimacy is moral justification. To show that a law is legitimate is therefore to show that it enjoys a kind of moral justification which is weaker than justice and which is compatible with its being unjust. So according to this second way of handling Rawls s example, the liberal does not say abortion is permitted by political morality because she bifurcates morality in a way that allows public and private senses of morally permissible to come apart. Rather, she says it because liberal political philosophy makes essential use of a moral concept, namely legitimate, which picks out one kind of moral justifiability that, it is hoped, even dissenters in the example think can be enjoyed by liberal abortion laws. So the concept of legitimacy enables the liberal political philosopher to salvage the claims that laws are mutually justifiable and have some moral claim on us without claiming that citizens are to regard the conduct they permit as morally permissible. Earlier, I quoted Jerry as saying [s]ocial morality raises problems similar to the traditional problems of liberal political philosophy. (p. 48) I have said that the liberal political philosopher faces a problem because mutually justifiable laws permit conduct that some citizens regard as morally impermissible. I have tried to show how the concept of legitimacy helps her address that problem. I believe that Jerry faces a similar problem, call it the permissibility problem. Rules of social morality which are publicly justified in his sense will permit behavior that some members of society may judge to be immoral. How are they to regard that behavior? Are they to think that permissibility is on the side of social morality, so they are to believe that conduct allowed by social morality is immoral but morally permissible? Are they to think that permissibility follows their private judgment, so that social morality permits conduct which is morally wrong? Here as before, I take the first option to be incoherent as it stands.

12 12 Jerry might argue that those who regard conduct as impermissible should change their view once they see that prohibitions on the conduct cannot be publicly justified in his sense. The difficulty with this response is that what prohibitions can and cannot be publicly justified depends upon the content of other people s evaluative sets. I may regard some of those people as deeply mistaken about morality. Suppose that I regard -ing as morally wrong and that I can produce reasons that I believe support the claim that it is. It is very hard to see why I should change my view about the truth-value of -ing is morally impermissible because other people even other reasonable people disagree with me on the basis of a comprehensive moral doctrine that I do not find convincing or even attractive. It is especially hard to see why I should do that if I am willing to abide by a set of justifiable conventions regarding my assertion of the sentences -ing is morally impermissible, You ought not and so on. Another way Jerry might handle the permissibility problem would be to adopt a variant of the bifurcation strategy. Jerry might assert another distinction within the ethical, perhaps congruent with the distinction drawn by what I called the first additional feature of social morality. He might say that each person is to regard social morality as one part of morality and her own standards for evaluating rightness, wrongness and permissibility of action as constituting another. He might then assert that moral permissibility has to be seen as part-dependent. We are to regard -ing as morally impermissible insofar as it is prohibited by our private morality and as morally permissible insofar as it is permitted by social morality. Jerry does not refer to private morality, but some of his turns of phrase suggest that the bifurcation, or better the n-furcation of morality into social and private moralities is not foreign to his thinking. He quotes with evident approval Kurt Baier s remark that a society s morality is the joint product of the morality of its individual members. (p. 389) And he speaks in his own voice of trying to adjudicate between rival views of morality[.] (p. 406) Perhaps with a little pushing, these remarks can be taken to suggest some sympathy for the thoughts that there are private and social moralities, and that the distinction can be pressed into service to handle the permissibility problem. But I do not think Jerry should rely on the n-furcation strategy. For one thing, the strategy would be highly controversial. Jerry may not have the political liberal s in-principle aversion to meta-ethical controversy as such, but he also may not want to fly in the face of our considered judgments. I think the part-dependence required by the n-furcation strategy would strike many people as mistaken or incoherent. In assessing my assertion, we should not be misled by the apparent relativism of many of our students. Their relativism consists in, or implies, that permissibility is agent-dependent: the same conduct can be permissible for others but not for me. Agent-dependence is not part-dependence. For part-dependence implies that the same conduct is impermissible for all agents by one part of morality and permissible for all agents according to another part. Once we see what part-dependence implies, we can see a puzzle that besets the n-furcation strategy. Suppose that social morality permits -ing while my private morality does not. Then if others, I may not reproach them because their conduct is permitted by social morality. So in the second- and third-person cases, the reasons social morality gives me not to reproach trump the reasons private morality gives me to reproach. But now suppose that I. Should I reproach myself? It would seem not, since social morality applies to me as well as to everyone else, and - ing is permitted by social morality. But -ing is also forbidden by my private morality and if I do

13 13 not reproach even myself for -ing, then I do not really hold my private morality at all. 9 So I should reproach myself because though -ing is permitted by social morality it is forbidden by private morality. In the first-person case, the reasons social morality provides me not to reproach are trumped by the reasons private morality gives me to reproach, even though social morality applies to me as it does to others. Because of the way social morality is publicly justified on Jerry s view, we might think that social morality is the source of what are often called agent-neutral reasons. But in fact there seems to be a kind of agent-relativity to the reasons provided by social morality. This is puzzling. I do not understand the reasons provided by social morality clearly enough to see why this is so. Jerry could address the permissibility problem by breaking the link between the moral permissibility of -ing and its being permitted by social morality. Taking social morality to include secondorder precepts can help him do that. For according to the proposal entertained earlier, to say that -ing is permitted by social morality is simply to say that the conventions or second-order precepts which govern our practices do not authorize anyone to call another to account for -ing. But as we saw earlier, is that this way of addressing the problem raises questions about social morality is a morality at all, or whether it is more like a code of etiquette. The similarities between liberal political philosophy and Jerry s project suggest a way of salvaging the claim that social morality is morality properly so called. I have said liberal political philosophy is able to accommodate talk of political morality, while eschewing the bifurcation strategy, because it makes essential use of a kind of moral justification that attaches to laws but is weaker than justice. Suppose either that we can find some justificatory concept which can do for Jerry s project what the concept of legitimacy does for liberal political philosophy, or that we can extend or transplant the concept of legitimacy from the political realm to the social. For simplicity s sake, I suppose the latter. Then Jerry could maintain that what regulates and is taken to regulate our social existence (p. 255) is set of first- and second-order precepts that enjoys legitimacy, perhaps because it solves coordination problems. As with legitimate laws so with precepts in the legitimate set, Jerry could maintain that everyone has a moral duty to go along with them. But he need not maintain that that is because the firstorder precepts themselves track what everyone takes or ought to take as the demands and permissions of morality. Because he need not maintain that the first-order precepts track in this way, the fact that the precepts of social morality permit some conduct does not raise the permissibility problem or commit Jerry to the conclusion that the permitted conduct should be taken to be morally permissible. It only shows that a set of precepts which enjoys the relevant sort of moral justification does not authorize anyone to issue imperatives prohibiting it. By extending the notion of legitimacy from the political, we can accommodate the claim that social morality is morality, in much the same way that the liberal political philosopher accommodates talk of political morality. Social morality is morality, not because it is an independent part of morality that provides reasons to reproach and refrain which are agent-relative in the puzzling way I spoke of a moment ago, but because it enjoys legitimacy and legitimacy is a kind of justification that is moral. 9 Morris Udall, the wit who represented part of Arizona in Congress for almost 30 years, once said of a prominent Catholic politician His religion is so private he won t even impose it on himself. If you get the joke, you get the point.

14 14 My suggestion that legitimacy be extended or transplanted from the political to the moral may not be viable. A lot of work would be required to see whether it is. And it may not be a suggestion that Jerry would welcome. The suggestion is, I believe, consistent with the amended version of the Takings Clause, though I shall not try to show that. But even if it is, that may not be enough. For Jerry implies in one passage that justified demands of social morality are to be acknowledged as moral demands. (p. 262, emphasis added) In another, he describes social morality as a moral code. (pp. 398ff.) The tenor of these remarks suggests that he might find my way of accommodating the description of social morality as a morality weak and unsatisfying. I think morality is an honorific. I want to guard it jealously and apply it sparingly. I do not want the precepts that specify moral duties and permissions to depend upon full information about the eligible sets of those who might be quite wrong, even if they are reasonable. Jerry may not regard morality as an honorific, but he too wants to apply the term sparingly. He does not want to attach it to sets of precepts that are inaccessible to some (p. 235) or that are backed only by reasons others cannot see. (pp. 16, 20, 322) Perhaps that is why he speaks of our evaluative standards (pp. 276ff.) and our private judgment about the demands of morality (p. 22) rather than of private morality or, as Baier does, of the moralit[ies] of [society s] individual members (p. 389). Claims about what reasons are and are not accessible, and about reasons the force of which others can and cannot see, have been at the heart of debates about public reasoning for a very long time. Despite their centrality, I believe that the conditions of accessibility, and the implications of inaccessibility, are not yet well understood. Those beliefs, and my differences with Jerry about them, are the ultimate sources of my questions about this terrific book. Paul Weithman Department of Philosophy University of Notre Dame

PRÉCIS THE ORDER OF PUBLIC REASON: A THEORY OF FREEDOM AND MORALITY IN A DIVERSE AND BOUNDED WORLD

PRÉCIS THE ORDER OF PUBLIC REASON: A THEORY OF FREEDOM AND MORALITY IN A DIVERSE AND BOUNDED WORLD EuJAP Vol. 9 No. 1 2013 PRÉCIS THE ORDER OF PUBLIC REASON: A THEORY OF FREEDOM AND MORALITY IN A DIVERSE AND BOUNDED WORLD GERALD GAUS University of Arizona This work advances a theory that forms a unified

More information

Comment on Martha Nussbaum s Purified Patriotism

Comment on Martha Nussbaum s Purified Patriotism Comment on Martha Nussbaum s Purified Patriotism Patriotism is generally thought to require a special attachment to the particular: to one s own country and to one s fellow citizens. It is therefore thought

More information

Comment on Robert Audi, Democratic Authority and the Separation of Church and State

Comment on Robert Audi, Democratic Authority and the Separation of Church and State Weithman 1. Comment on Robert Audi, Democratic Authority and the Separation of Church and State Among the tasks of liberal democratic theory are the identification and defense of political principles that

More information

The fact that some action, A, is part of a valuable and eligible pattern of action, P, is a reason to perform A. 1

The fact that some action, A, is part of a valuable and eligible pattern of action, P, is a reason to perform A. 1 The Common Structure of Kantianism and Act Consequentialism Christopher Woodard RoME 2009 1. My thesis is that Kantian ethics and Act Consequentialism share a common structure, since both can be well understood

More information

Rescuing Public Justification from Public Reason Liberalism

Rescuing Public Justification from Public Reason Liberalism June 29th, 2017 The final version of this article will be published in Oxford Studies in Political Philosophy Vol. 5. Rescuing Public Justification from Public Reason Liberalism Fabian Wendt Public reason

More information

In Epistemic Relativism, Mark Kalderon defends a view that has become

In Epistemic Relativism, Mark Kalderon defends a view that has become Aporia vol. 24 no. 1 2014 Incoherence in Epistemic Relativism I. Introduction In Epistemic Relativism, Mark Kalderon defends a view that has become increasingly popular across various academic disciplines.

More information

Public Reason in the Open Society

Public Reason in the Open Society KEVIN VALLIER Department of Philosophy Bowling Green State University 305 Shatzel Hall Bowling Green, OH 43403 Email: kevinvallier@gmail.com Web: http://www.kevinvallier.com 38 A TENSION IN THE IDEA OF

More information

A Contractualist Reply

A Contractualist Reply A Contractualist Reply The Harvard community has made this article openly available. Please share how this access benefits you. Your story matters Citation Scanlon, T. M. 2008. A Contractualist Reply.

More information

CONVENTIONALISM AND NORMATIVITY

CONVENTIONALISM AND NORMATIVITY 1 CONVENTIONALISM AND NORMATIVITY TORBEN SPAAK We have seen (in Section 3) that Hart objects to Austin s command theory of law, that it cannot account for the normativity of law, and that what is missing

More information

Choosing Rationally and Choosing Correctly *

Choosing Rationally and Choosing Correctly * Choosing Rationally and Choosing Correctly * Ralph Wedgwood 1 Two views of practical reason Suppose that you are faced with several different options (that is, several ways in which you might act in a

More information

Convergence liberalism and the problem of disagreement concerning public justification*

Convergence liberalism and the problem of disagreement concerning public justification* Convergence liberalism and the problem of disagreement concerning public justification* Paul Billingham Christ Church, University of Oxford Abstract The convergence conception of political liberalism has

More information

Seth Mayer. Comments on Christopher McCammon s Is Liberal Legitimacy Utopian?

Seth Mayer. Comments on Christopher McCammon s Is Liberal Legitimacy Utopian? Seth Mayer Comments on Christopher McCammon s Is Liberal Legitimacy Utopian? Christopher McCammon s defense of Liberal Legitimacy hopes to give a negative answer to the question posed by the title of his

More information

KANTIAN ETHICS (Dan Gaskill)

KANTIAN ETHICS (Dan Gaskill) KANTIAN ETHICS (Dan Gaskill) German philosopher Immanuel Kant (1724-1804) was an opponent of utilitarianism. Basic Summary: Kant, unlike Mill, believed that certain types of actions (including murder,

More information

KANT, MORAL DUTY AND THE DEMANDS OF PURE PRACTICAL REASON. The law is reason unaffected by desire.

KANT, MORAL DUTY AND THE DEMANDS OF PURE PRACTICAL REASON. The law is reason unaffected by desire. KANT, MORAL DUTY AND THE DEMANDS OF PURE PRACTICAL REASON The law is reason unaffected by desire. Aristotle, Politics Book III (1287a32) THE BIG IDEAS TO MASTER Kantian formalism Kantian constructivism

More information

Positivism, Natural Law, and Disestablishment: Some Questions Raised by MacCormick's Moralistic Amoralism

Positivism, Natural Law, and Disestablishment: Some Questions Raised by MacCormick's Moralistic Amoralism Valparaiso University Law Review Volume 20 Number 1 pp.55-60 Fall 1985 Positivism, Natural Law, and Disestablishment: Some Questions Raised by MacCormick's Moralistic Amoralism Joseph M. Boyle Jr. Recommended

More information

THE NATURE OF NORMATIVITY IN KANT S PHILOSOPHY OF LOGIC REBECCA V. MILLSOP S

THE NATURE OF NORMATIVITY IN KANT S PHILOSOPHY OF LOGIC REBECCA V. MILLSOP S THE NATURE OF NORMATIVITY IN KANT S PHILOSOPHY OF LOGIC REBECCA V. MILLSOP S I. INTRODUCTION Immanuel Kant claims that logic is constitutive of thought: without [the laws of logic] we would not think at

More information

The Rightness Error: An Evaluation of Normative Ethics in the Absence of Moral Realism

The Rightness Error: An Evaluation of Normative Ethics in the Absence of Moral Realism An Evaluation of Normative Ethics in the Absence of Moral Realism Mathais Sarrazin J.L. Mackie s Error Theory postulates that all normative claims are false. It does this based upon his denial of moral

More information

PROVOCATION EVERYONE IS A PHILOSOPHER! T.M. Scanlon

PROVOCATION EVERYONE IS A PHILOSOPHER! T.M. Scanlon PROVOCATION EVERYONE IS A PHILOSOPHER! T.M. Scanlon In the first chapter of his book, Reading Obama, 1 Professor James Kloppenberg offers an account of the intellectual climate at Harvard Law School during

More information

Two Kinds of Ends in Themselves in Kant s Moral Theory

Two Kinds of Ends in Themselves in Kant s Moral Theory Western University Scholarship@Western 2015 Undergraduate Awards The Undergraduate Awards 2015 Two Kinds of Ends in Themselves in Kant s Moral Theory David Hakim Western University, davidhakim266@gmail.com

More information

TWO VERSIONS OF HUME S LAW

TWO VERSIONS OF HUME S LAW DISCUSSION NOTE BY CAMPBELL BROWN JOURNAL OF ETHICS & SOCIAL PHILOSOPHY DISCUSSION NOTE MAY 2015 URL: WWW.JESP.ORG COPYRIGHT CAMPBELL BROWN 2015 Two Versions of Hume s Law MORAL CONCLUSIONS CANNOT VALIDLY

More information

Notes on Moore and Parker, Chapter 12: Moral, Legal and Aesthetic Reasoning

Notes on Moore and Parker, Chapter 12: Moral, Legal and Aesthetic Reasoning Notes on Moore and Parker, Chapter 12: Moral, Legal and Aesthetic Reasoning The final chapter of Moore and Parker s text is devoted to how we might apply critical reasoning in certain philosophical contexts.

More information

Practical Rationality and Ethics. Basic Terms and Positions

Practical Rationality and Ethics. Basic Terms and Positions Practical Rationality and Ethics Basic Terms and Positions Practical reasons and moral ought Reasons are given in answer to the sorts of questions ethics seeks to answer: What should I do? How should I

More information

Does Deduction really rest on a more secure epistemological footing than Induction?

Does Deduction really rest on a more secure epistemological footing than Induction? Does Deduction really rest on a more secure epistemological footing than Induction? We argue that, if deduction is taken to at least include classical logic (CL, henceforth), justifying CL - and thus deduction

More information

Reply to Kit Fine. Theodore Sider July 19, 2013

Reply to Kit Fine. Theodore Sider July 19, 2013 Reply to Kit Fine Theodore Sider July 19, 2013 Kit Fine s paper raises important and difficult issues about my approach to the metaphysics of fundamentality. In chapters 7 and 8 I examined certain subtle

More information

Ethics is subjective.

Ethics is subjective. Introduction Scientific Method and Research Ethics Ethical Theory Greg Bognar Stockholm University September 22, 2017 Ethics is subjective. If ethics is subjective, then moral claims are subjective in

More information

On the Relevance of Ignorance to the Demands of Morality 1

On the Relevance of Ignorance to the Demands of Morality 1 3 On the Relevance of Ignorance to the Demands of Morality 1 Geoffrey Sayre-McCord It is impossible to overestimate the amount of stupidity in the world. Bernard Gert 2 Introduction In Morality, Bernard

More information

HAVE WE REASON TO DO AS RATIONALITY REQUIRES? A COMMENT ON RAZ

HAVE WE REASON TO DO AS RATIONALITY REQUIRES? A COMMENT ON RAZ HAVE WE REASON TO DO AS RATIONALITY REQUIRES? A COMMENT ON RAZ BY JOHN BROOME JOURNAL OF ETHICS & SOCIAL PHILOSOPHY SYMPOSIUM I DECEMBER 2005 URL: WWW.JESP.ORG COPYRIGHT JOHN BROOME 2005 HAVE WE REASON

More information

To link to this article:

To link to this article: This article was downloaded by: [University of Chicago Library] On: 24 May 2013, At: 08:10 Publisher: Routledge Informa Ltd Registered in England and Wales Registered Number: 1072954 Registered office:

More information

MULTI-PEER DISAGREEMENT AND THE PREFACE PARADOX. Kenneth Boyce and Allan Hazlett

MULTI-PEER DISAGREEMENT AND THE PREFACE PARADOX. Kenneth Boyce and Allan Hazlett MULTI-PEER DISAGREEMENT AND THE PREFACE PARADOX Kenneth Boyce and Allan Hazlett Abstract The problem of multi-peer disagreement concerns the reasonable response to a situation in which you believe P1 Pn

More information

Moral dilemmas. Digital Lingnan University. Lingnan University. Gopal Shyam NAIR

Moral dilemmas. Digital Lingnan University. Lingnan University. Gopal Shyam NAIR Lingnan University Digital Commons @ Lingnan University Staff Publications Lingnan Staff Publication 1-1-2015 Moral dilemmas Gopal Shyam NAIR Follow this and additional works at: http://commons.ln.edu.hk/sw_master

More information

Philosophy in Review XXXIII (2013), no. 5

Philosophy in Review XXXIII (2013), no. 5 Robert Stern Understanding Moral Obligation. Kant, Hegel, Kierkegaard. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press 2012. 277 pages $90.00 (cloth ISBN 978 1 107 01207 3) In his thoroughly researched and tightly

More information

Are There Reasons to Be Rational?

Are There Reasons to Be Rational? Are There Reasons to Be Rational? Olav Gjelsvik, University of Oslo The thesis. Among people writing about rationality, few people are more rational than Wlodek Rabinowicz. But are there reasons for being

More information

Oxford Scholarship Online Abstracts and Keywords

Oxford Scholarship Online Abstracts and Keywords Oxford Scholarship Online Abstracts and Keywords ISBN 9780198802693 Title The Value of Rationality Author(s) Ralph Wedgwood Book abstract Book keywords Rationality is a central concept for epistemology,

More information

BELIEF POLICIES, by Paul Helm. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, Pp. xiii and 226. $54.95 (Cloth).

BELIEF POLICIES, by Paul Helm. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, Pp. xiii and 226. $54.95 (Cloth). BELIEF POLICIES, by Paul Helm. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1994. Pp. xiii and 226. $54.95 (Cloth). TRENTON MERRICKS, Virginia Commonwealth University Faith and Philosophy 13 (1996): 449-454

More information

Kantian Constructivism, Baseball and Christian Ethics. part of it, about physics, about morality or some of its parts, about reasons or normativity.

Kantian Constructivism, Baseball and Christian Ethics. part of it, about physics, about morality or some of its parts, about reasons or normativity. Kantian Constructivism, Baseball and Christian Ethics One can be a constructivist about any or all of a number of domains: about mathematics or some part of it, about physics, about morality or some of

More information

Evaluating actions The principle of utility Strengths Criticisms Act vs. rule

Evaluating actions The principle of utility Strengths Criticisms Act vs. rule UTILITARIAN ETHICS Evaluating actions The principle of utility Strengths Criticisms Act vs. rule A dilemma You are a lawyer. You have a client who is an old lady who owns a big house. She tells you that

More information

THE SENSE OF FREEDOM 1. Dana K. Nelkin. I. Introduction. abandon even in the face of powerful arguments that this sense is illusory.

THE SENSE OF FREEDOM 1. Dana K. Nelkin. I. Introduction. abandon even in the face of powerful arguments that this sense is illusory. THE SENSE OF FREEDOM 1 Dana K. Nelkin I. Introduction We appear to have an inescapable sense that we are free, a sense that we cannot abandon even in the face of powerful arguments that this sense is illusory.

More information

McCLOSKEY ON RATIONAL ENDS: The Dilemma of Intuitionism

McCLOSKEY ON RATIONAL ENDS: The Dilemma of Intuitionism 48 McCLOSKEY ON RATIONAL ENDS: The Dilemma of Intuitionism T om R egan In his book, Meta-Ethics and Normative Ethics,* Professor H. J. McCloskey sets forth an argument which he thinks shows that we know,

More information

Class #14: October 13 Gödel s Platonism

Class #14: October 13 Gödel s Platonism Philosophy 405: Knowledge, Truth and Mathematics Fall 2010 Hamilton College Russell Marcus Class #14: October 13 Gödel s Platonism I. The Continuum Hypothesis and Its Independence The continuum problem

More information

Philosophy 1100: Ethics

Philosophy 1100: Ethics Philosophy 1100: Ethics Topic 7: Ross Theory of Prima Facie Duties 1. Something all our theories have had in common 2. W.D. Ross 3. The Concept of a Prima Facie Duty 4. Ross List of Prima Facie Duties

More information

(i) Morality is a system; and (ii) It is a system comprised of moral rules and principles.

(i) Morality is a system; and (ii) It is a system comprised of moral rules and principles. Ethics and Morality Ethos (Greek) and Mores (Latin) are terms having to do with custom, habit, and behavior. Ethics is the study of morality. This definition raises two questions: (a) What is morality?

More information

NOTES ON WILLIAMSON: CHAPTER 11 ASSERTION Constitutive Rules

NOTES ON WILLIAMSON: CHAPTER 11 ASSERTION Constitutive Rules NOTES ON WILLIAMSON: CHAPTER 11 ASSERTION 11.1 Constitutive Rules Chapter 11 is not a general scrutiny of all of the norms governing assertion. Assertions may be subject to many different norms. Some norms

More information

HART ON THE INTERNAL ASPECT OF RULES

HART ON THE INTERNAL ASPECT OF RULES HART ON THE INTERNAL ASPECT OF RULES John D. Hodson Introduction, Polycarp Ikuenobe THE CONTEMPORARY AMERICAN PHILOSOPHER John Hodson, examines what H. L. A. Hart means by the notion of internal aspect

More information

Molinism and divine prophecy of free actions

Molinism and divine prophecy of free actions Molinism and divine prophecy of free actions GRAHAM OPPY School of Philosophical, Historical and International Studies, Monash University, Clayton Campus, Wellington Road, Clayton VIC 3800 AUSTRALIA Graham.Oppy@monash.edu

More information

Right-Making, Reference, and Reduction

Right-Making, Reference, and Reduction Right-Making, Reference, and Reduction Kent State University BIBLID [0873-626X (2014) 39; pp. 139-145] Abstract The causal theory of reference (CTR) provides a well-articulated and widely-accepted account

More information

Computer Ethics. Normative Ethics and Normative Argumentation. Viola Schiaffonati October 10 th 2017

Computer Ethics. Normative Ethics and Normative Argumentation. Viola Schiaffonati October 10 th 2017 Normative Ethics and Normative Argumentation Viola Schiaffonati October 10 th 2017 Overview (van de Poel and Royakkers 2011) 2 Some essential concepts Ethical theories Relativism and absolutism Consequentialist

More information

CRUCIAL TOPICS IN THE DEBATE ABOUT THE EXISTENCE OF EXTERNAL REASONS

CRUCIAL TOPICS IN THE DEBATE ABOUT THE EXISTENCE OF EXTERNAL REASONS CRUCIAL TOPICS IN THE DEBATE ABOUT THE EXISTENCE OF EXTERNAL REASONS By MARANATHA JOY HAYES A THESIS PRESENTED TO THE GRADUATE SCHOOL OF THE UNIVERSITY OF FLORIDA IN PARTIAL FULFILLMENT OF THE REQUIREMENTS

More information

Unifying the Categorical Imperative* Marcus Arvan University of Tampa

Unifying the Categorical Imperative* Marcus Arvan University of Tampa Unifying the Categorical Imperative* Marcus Arvan University of Tampa [T]he concept of freedom constitutes the keystone of the whole structure of a system of pure reason [and] this idea reveals itself

More information

Truth and Molinism * Trenton Merricks. Molinism: The Contemporary Debate edited by Ken Perszyk. Oxford University Press, 2011.

Truth and Molinism * Trenton Merricks. Molinism: The Contemporary Debate edited by Ken Perszyk. Oxford University Press, 2011. Truth and Molinism * Trenton Merricks Molinism: The Contemporary Debate edited by Ken Perszyk. Oxford University Press, 2011. According to Luis de Molina, God knows what each and every possible human would

More information

AUTONOMY, TAKING ONE S CHOICES TO BE GOOD, AND PRACTICAL LAW: REPLIES TO CRITICS

AUTONOMY, TAKING ONE S CHOICES TO BE GOOD, AND PRACTICAL LAW: REPLIES TO CRITICS Philosophical Books Vol. 49 No. 2 April 2008 pp. 125 137 AUTONOMY, TAKING ONE S CHOICES TO BE GOOD, AND PRACTICAL LAW: REPLIES TO CRITICS andrews reath The University of California, Riverside I Several

More information

Reply to Gauthier and Gibbard

Reply to Gauthier and Gibbard Reply to Gauthier and Gibbard The Harvard community has made this article openly available. Please share how this access benefits you. Your story matters Citation Scanlon, Thomas M. 2003. Reply to Gauthier

More information

-- The search text of this PDF is generated from uncorrected OCR text.

-- The search text of this PDF is generated from uncorrected OCR text. Citation: 21 Isr. L. Rev. 113 1986 Content downloaded/printed from HeinOnline (http://heinonline.org) Sun Jan 11 12:34:09 2015 -- Your use of this HeinOnline PDF indicates your acceptance of HeinOnline's

More information

Hume s Law Violated? Rik Peels. The Journal of Value Inquiry ISSN J Value Inquiry DOI /s

Hume s Law Violated? Rik Peels. The Journal of Value Inquiry ISSN J Value Inquiry DOI /s Rik Peels The Journal of Value Inquiry ISSN 0022-5363 J Value Inquiry DOI 10.1007/s10790-014-9439-8 1 23 Your article is protected by copyright and all rights are held exclusively by Springer Science +Business

More information

moral absolutism agents moral responsibility

moral absolutism agents moral responsibility Moral luck Last time we discussed the question of whether there could be such a thing as objectively right actions -- actions which are right, independently of relativization to the standards of any particular

More information

Philosophical Ethics. The nature of ethical analysis. Discussion based on Johnson, Computer Ethics, Chapter 2.

Philosophical Ethics. The nature of ethical analysis. Discussion based on Johnson, Computer Ethics, Chapter 2. Philosophical Ethics The nature of ethical analysis Discussion based on Johnson, Computer Ethics, Chapter 2. How to resolve ethical issues? censorship abortion affirmative action How do we defend our moral

More information

In Kant s Conception of Humanity, Joshua Glasgow defends a traditional reading of

In Kant s Conception of Humanity, Joshua Glasgow defends a traditional reading of Glasgow s Conception of Kantian Humanity Richard Dean ABSTRACT: In Kant s Conception of Humanity, Joshua Glasgow defends a traditional reading of the humanity formulation of the Categorical Imperative.

More information

Is euthanasia morally permissible? What is the relationship between patient autonomy,

Is euthanasia morally permissible? What is the relationship between patient autonomy, Course Syllabus PHILOSOPHY 433 Instructor: Doran Smolkin, Ph. D. doran.smolkin@kpu.ca or doran.smolkin@ubc.ca Course Description: Is euthanasia morally permissible? What is the relationship between patient

More information

Moral Relativism and Conceptual Analysis. David J. Chalmers

Moral Relativism and Conceptual Analysis. David J. Chalmers Moral Relativism and Conceptual Analysis David J. Chalmers An Inconsistent Triad (1) All truths are a priori entailed by fundamental truths (2) No moral truths are a priori entailed by fundamental truths

More information

REASON AND PRACTICAL-REGRET. Nate Wahrenberger, College of William and Mary

REASON AND PRACTICAL-REGRET. Nate Wahrenberger, College of William and Mary 1 REASON AND PRACTICAL-REGRET Nate Wahrenberger, College of William and Mary Abstract: Christine Korsgaard argues that a practical reason (that is, a reason that counts in favor of an action) must motivate

More information

What God Could Have Made

What God Could Have Made 1 What God Could Have Made By Heimir Geirsson and Michael Losonsky I. Introduction Atheists have argued that if there is a God who is omnipotent, omniscient and omnibenevolent, then God would have made

More information

On the Rawlsian Anthropology and the "Autonomous" Account

On the Rawlsian Anthropology and the Autonomous Account University of Windsor Scholarship at UWindsor Critical Reflections Essays of Significance & Critical Reflections 2017 Mar 31st, 10:30 AM - 11:00 AM On the Rawlsian Anthropology and the "Autonomous" Account

More information

DISCUSSION THE GUISE OF A REASON

DISCUSSION THE GUISE OF A REASON NADEEM J.Z. HUSSAIN DISCUSSION THE GUISE OF A REASON The articles collected in David Velleman s The Possibility of Practical Reason are a snapshot or rather a film-strip of part of a philosophical endeavour

More information

Instrumental reasoning* John Broome

Instrumental reasoning* John Broome Instrumental reasoning* John Broome For: Rationality, Rules and Structure, edited by Julian Nida-Rümelin and Wolfgang Spohn, Kluwer. * This paper was written while I was a visiting fellow at the Swedish

More information

HANDBOOK (New or substantially modified material appears in boxes.)

HANDBOOK (New or substantially modified material appears in boxes.) 1 HANDBOOK (New or substantially modified material appears in boxes.) I. ARGUMENT RECOGNITION Important Concepts An argument is a unit of reasoning that attempts to prove that a certain idea is true by

More information

Jean Jacques Rousseau The Social Contract, or Principles of Political Right (1762)

Jean Jacques Rousseau The Social Contract, or Principles of Political Right (1762) Jean Jacques Rousseau The Social Contract, or Principles of Political Right (1762) Source: http://www.constitution.org/jjr/socon.htm Excerpts from Book I BOOK I [In this book] I mean to inquire if, in

More information

Self-Evidence and A Priori Moral Knowledge

Self-Evidence and A Priori Moral Knowledge Self-Evidence and A Priori Moral Knowledge Colorado State University BIBLID [0873-626X (2012) 33; pp. 459-467] Abstract According to rationalists about moral knowledge, some moral truths are knowable a

More information

METAETHICAL MORAL RELATIVISM AND THE ANALOGY WITH PHYSICS

METAETHICAL MORAL RELATIVISM AND THE ANALOGY WITH PHYSICS Praxis, Vol. 1, No. 1, Spring 2008 ISSN 1756-1019 METAETHICAL MORAL RELATIVISM AND THE ANALOGY WITH PHYSICS ALEXANDRE ERLER LINCOLN COLLEGE, OXFORD Abstract This paper deals with a specific version of

More information

An Introduction to Ethics / Moral Philosophy

An Introduction to Ethics / Moral Philosophy An Introduction to Ethics / Moral Philosophy Ethics / moral philosophy is concerned with what is good for individuals and society and is also described as moral philosophy. The term is derived from the

More information

Kantian Humility and Ontological Categories Sam Cowling University of Massachusetts, Amherst

Kantian Humility and Ontological Categories Sam Cowling University of Massachusetts, Amherst Kantian Humility and Ontological Categories Sam Cowling University of Massachusetts, Amherst [Forthcoming in Analysis. Penultimate Draft. Cite published version.] Kantian Humility holds that agents like

More information

A CONSEQUENTIALIST RESPONSE TO THE DEMANDINGNESS OBJECTION Nicholas R. Baker, Lee University THE DEMANDS OF ACT CONSEQUENTIALISM

A CONSEQUENTIALIST RESPONSE TO THE DEMANDINGNESS OBJECTION Nicholas R. Baker, Lee University THE DEMANDS OF ACT CONSEQUENTIALISM 1 A CONSEQUENTIALIST RESPONSE TO THE DEMANDINGNESS OBJECTION Nicholas R. Baker, Lee University INTRODUCTION We usually believe that morality has limits; that is, that there is some limit to what morality

More information

Understanding Belief Reports. David Braun. In this paper, I defend a well-known theory of belief reports from an important objection.

Understanding Belief Reports. David Braun. In this paper, I defend a well-known theory of belief reports from an important objection. Appeared in Philosophical Review 105 (1998), pp. 555-595. Understanding Belief Reports David Braun In this paper, I defend a well-known theory of belief reports from an important objection. The theory

More information

Judith Jarvis Thomson s Normativity

Judith Jarvis Thomson s Normativity Judith Jarvis Thomson s Normativity Gilbert Harman June 28, 2010 Normativity is a careful, rigorous account of the meanings of basic normative terms like good, virtue, correct, ought, should, and must.

More information

WHY RELATIVISM IS NOT SELF-REFUTING IN ANY INTERESTING WAY

WHY RELATIVISM IS NOT SELF-REFUTING IN ANY INTERESTING WAY Preliminary draft, WHY RELATIVISM IS NOT SELF-REFUTING IN ANY INTERESTING WAY Is relativism really self-refuting? This paper takes a look at some frequently used arguments and its preliminary answer to

More information

A CONTRACTUALIST READING OF KANT S PROOF OF THE FORMULA OF HUMANITY. Adam Cureton

A CONTRACTUALIST READING OF KANT S PROOF OF THE FORMULA OF HUMANITY. Adam Cureton A CONTRACTUALIST READING OF KANT S PROOF OF THE FORMULA OF HUMANITY Adam Cureton Abstract: Kant offers the following argument for the Formula of Humanity: Each rational agent necessarily conceives of her

More information

[Forthcoming in The International Encyclopedia of Ethics, ed. Hugh LaFollette. (Oxford: Blackwell), 2012] Imperatives, Categorical and Hypothetical

[Forthcoming in The International Encyclopedia of Ethics, ed. Hugh LaFollette. (Oxford: Blackwell), 2012] Imperatives, Categorical and Hypothetical [Forthcoming in The International Encyclopedia of Ethics, ed. Hugh LaFollette. (Oxford: Blackwell), 2012] Imperatives, Categorical and Hypothetical Samuel J. Kerstein Ethicists distinguish between categorical

More information

How to Write a Philosophy Paper

How to Write a Philosophy Paper How to Write a Philosophy Paper The goal of a philosophy paper is simple: make a compelling argument. This guide aims to teach you how to write philosophy papers, starting from the ground up. To do that,

More information

Phil 108, August 10, 2010 Punishment

Phil 108, August 10, 2010 Punishment Phil 108, August 10, 2010 Punishment Retributivism and Utilitarianism The retributive theory: (1) It is good in itself that those who have acted wrongly should suffer. When this happens, people get what

More information

Course Syllabus. Course Description: Objectives for this course include: PHILOSOPHY 333

Course Syllabus. Course Description: Objectives for this course include: PHILOSOPHY 333 Course Syllabus PHILOSOPHY 333 Instructor: Doran Smolkin, Ph. D. doran.smolkin@ubc.ca or doran.smolkin@kpu.ca Course Description: Is euthanasia morally permissible? What is the relationship between patient

More information

Society for Lesbian and Gay Philosophy American Philosophical Association, Eastern Division Meeting, 2009

Society for Lesbian and Gay Philosophy American Philosophical Association, Eastern Division Meeting, 2009 SOME OF MY BEST FRIENDS TEACH AT CALVIN COLLEGE RELIGIOUS IDENTITY AND SEXUAL-ORIENTATION DISCRIMINATION Society for Lesbian and Gay Philosophy American Philosophical Association, Eastern Division Meeting,

More information

Remarks on a Foundationalist Theory of Truth. Anil Gupta University of Pittsburgh

Remarks on a Foundationalist Theory of Truth. Anil Gupta University of Pittsburgh For Philosophy and Phenomenological Research Remarks on a Foundationalist Theory of Truth Anil Gupta University of Pittsburgh I Tim Maudlin s Truth and Paradox offers a theory of truth that arises from

More information

The Conflict Between Authority and Autonomy from Robert Wolff, In Defense of Anarchism (1970)

The Conflict Between Authority and Autonomy from Robert Wolff, In Defense of Anarchism (1970) The Conflict Between Authority and Autonomy from Robert Wolff, In Defense of Anarchism (1970) 1. The Concept of Authority Politics is the exercise of the power of the state, or the attempt to influence

More information

xiv Truth Without Objectivity

xiv Truth Without Objectivity Introduction There is a certain approach to theorizing about language that is called truthconditional semantics. The underlying idea of truth-conditional semantics is often summarized as the idea that

More information

HANDBOOK (New or substantially modified material appears in boxes.)

HANDBOOK (New or substantially modified material appears in boxes.) 1 HANDBOOK (New or substantially modified material appears in boxes.) I. ARGUMENT RECOGNITION Important Concepts An argument is a unit of reasoning that attempts to prove that a certain idea is true by

More information

In Defense of The Wide-Scope Instrumental Principle. Simon Rippon

In Defense of The Wide-Scope Instrumental Principle. Simon Rippon In Defense of The Wide-Scope Instrumental Principle Simon Rippon Suppose that people always have reason to take the means to the ends that they intend. 1 Then it would appear that people s intentions to

More information

Boghossian & Harman on the analytic theory of the a priori

Boghossian & Harman on the analytic theory of the a priori Boghossian & Harman on the analytic theory of the a priori PHIL 83104 November 2, 2011 Both Boghossian and Harman address themselves to the question of whether our a priori knowledge can be explained in

More information

Freedom's Law: The Moral Reading of the American Constitution.

Freedom's Law: The Moral Reading of the American Constitution. Freedom's Law: The Moral Reading of the American Constitution. By Ronald Dworkin. Cambridge: Harvard University Press, 1996.389 pp. Kenneth Einar Himma University of Washington In Freedom's Law, Ronald

More information

In Defense of Radical Empiricism. Joseph Benjamin Riegel. Chapel Hill 2006

In Defense of Radical Empiricism. Joseph Benjamin Riegel. Chapel Hill 2006 In Defense of Radical Empiricism Joseph Benjamin Riegel A thesis submitted to the faculty of the University of North Carolina at Chapel Hill in partial fulfillment of the requirements for the degree of

More information

From the Categorical Imperative to the Moral Law

From the Categorical Imperative to the Moral Law From the Categorical Imperative to the Moral Law Marianne Vahl Master Thesis in Philosophy Supervisor Olav Gjelsvik Department of Philosophy, Classics, History of Arts and Ideas UNIVERSITY OF OSLO May

More information

Philosophical Issues, vol. 8 (1997), pp

Philosophical Issues, vol. 8 (1997), pp Philosophical Issues, vol. 8 (1997), pp. 313-323. Different Kinds of Kind Terms: A Reply to Sosa and Kim 1 by Geoffrey Sayre-McCord University of North Carolina at Chapel Hill In "'Good' on Twin Earth"

More information

PHIL 202: IV:

PHIL 202: IV: Draft of 3-6- 13 PHIL 202: Core Ethics; Winter 2013 Core Sequence in the History of Ethics, 2011-2013 IV: 19 th and 20 th Century Moral Philosophy David O. Brink Handout #9: W.D. Ross Like other members

More information

SANDEL ON RELIGION IN THE PUBLIC SQUARE

SANDEL ON RELIGION IN THE PUBLIC SQUARE SANDEL ON RELIGION IN THE PUBLIC SQUARE Hugh Baxter For Boston University School of Law s Conference on Michael Sandel s Justice October 14, 2010 In the final chapter of Justice, Sandel calls for a new

More information

Blame and Forfeiture. The central issue that a theory of punishment must address is why we are we permitted to

Blame and Forfeiture. The central issue that a theory of punishment must address is why we are we permitted to Andy Engen Blame and Forfeiture The central issue that a theory of punishment must address is why we are we permitted to treat criminals in ways that would normally be impermissible, denying them of goods

More information

Luminosity, Reliability, and the Sorites

Luminosity, Reliability, and the Sorites Philosophy and Phenomenological Research Vol. LXXXI No. 3, November 2010 2010 Philosophy and Phenomenological Research, LLC Luminosity, Reliability, and the Sorites STEWART COHEN University of Arizona

More information

British Journal for the Philosophy of Science, 62 (2011), doi: /bjps/axr026

British Journal for the Philosophy of Science, 62 (2011), doi: /bjps/axr026 British Journal for the Philosophy of Science, 62 (2011), 899-907 doi:10.1093/bjps/axr026 URL: Please cite published version only. REVIEW

More information

Louisiana Law Review. Cheney C. Joseph Jr. Louisiana State University Law Center. Volume 35 Number 5 Special Issue Repository Citation

Louisiana Law Review. Cheney C. Joseph Jr. Louisiana State University Law Center. Volume 35 Number 5 Special Issue Repository Citation Louisiana Law Review Volume 35 Number 5 Special Issue 1975 ON GUILT, RESPONSIBILITY AND PUNISHMENT. By Alf Ross. Translated from Danish by Alastair Hannay and Thomas E. Sheahan. London, Stevens and Sons

More information

THE LARGER LOGICAL PICTURE

THE LARGER LOGICAL PICTURE THE LARGER LOGICAL PICTURE 1. ILLOCUTIONARY ACTS In this paper, I am concerned to articulate a conceptual framework which accommodates speech acts, or language acts, as well as logical theories. I will

More information

Prompt: Explain van Inwagen s consequence argument. Describe what you think is the best response

Prompt: Explain van Inwagen s consequence argument. Describe what you think is the best response Prompt: Explain van Inwagen s consequence argument. Describe what you think is the best response to this argument. Does this response succeed in saving compatibilism from the consequence argument? Why

More information

THE FREGE-GEACH PROBLEM AND KALDERON S MORAL FICTIONALISM. Matti Eklund Cornell University

THE FREGE-GEACH PROBLEM AND KALDERON S MORAL FICTIONALISM. Matti Eklund Cornell University THE FREGE-GEACH PROBLEM AND KALDERON S MORAL FICTIONALISM Matti Eklund Cornell University [me72@cornell.edu] Penultimate draft. Final version forthcoming in Philosophical Quarterly I. INTRODUCTION In his

More information

Ayer on the criterion of verifiability

Ayer on the criterion of verifiability Ayer on the criterion of verifiability November 19, 2004 1 The critique of metaphysics............................. 1 2 Observation statements............................... 2 3 In principle verifiability...............................

More information

WHY THERE REALLY ARE NO IRREDUCIBLY NORMATIVE PROPERTIES

WHY THERE REALLY ARE NO IRREDUCIBLY NORMATIVE PROPERTIES WHY THERE REALLY ARE NO IRREDUCIBLY NORMATIVE PROPERTIES Bart Streumer b.streumer@rug.nl In David Bakhurst, Brad Hooker and Margaret Little (eds.), Thinking About Reasons: Essays in Honour of Jonathan

More information